{"title":"<i>Dark Matters: Pessimism and the Problem of Suffering</i>","authors":"James Foster","doi":"10.1215/00318108-10469577","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"In Dark Matters, Mara Van Der Lugt attempts to rehabilitate pessimism as a moral stance. Critical to this task is the distinction between what she calls “future-oriented” and “value-oriented” pessimism (10). The former is what most people presently understand the word pessimism to mean: a gloomy view about the future, an attitude of premature defeat.Although this kind of fatalism can be found alongside value-oriented pessimism, Van Der Lugt is chiefly interested in the latter, which she portrays as a sympathetic appreciation of suffering that, although not without hope, does not attempt to explain—let alone explain away—the existence of evil.To make this case, Dark Matters proceeds in three sections. The first section, comprising the introduction and first two chapters of the book, sets up the contrast between future- and value-oriented pessimism by examining various approaches to the classic problem of evil, as summarized by Epicurus’s classic trilemma among God’s power, God’s goodness, and the existence of evil.Some of these are what she calls “negative” strategies, which deny the premise that there is evil—or, more generously, a problematic amount of evil—in the world (33). And some are “positive” strategies, which accept the premise of evil in the world but attempt to explain the origin of evil by, for example, casting it as the inevitable side effect of free will and/or sin (35). Whatever their views about the future, those who take up these strategies are, in Van Der Lugt’s terms, “optimists.” And they are so by virtue of believing the problem of evil can be satisfactorily answered.On the other hand, those who take the contrasting approach, believing that the problem of evil is so acute that it cannot be rationally resolved, are pessimists. And first among them, for Van Der Lugt’s purposes, is Pierre Bayle, who set the terms of the pessimist/optimist debate in the early modern era by making the problem of evil primarily a problem of suffering.For Bayle, the primary task of addressing Epicurus’s query is not to justify or undermine belief in the existence of a good God. It is, rather, to understand, or at least appreciate, the irrefutable experience of human suffering. This focus on suffering alone does not make Bayle a pessimist. Rather, what makes him a pessimist is his insistence that there is far more suffering than pleasure in life, that we have little power to choose whether we suffer or flourish in any given circumstance, and that most of our pains cannot be explained as just punishment.In opposing Bayle’s diagnosis, Van Der Lugt suggests that most optimists employ a rhetorical strategy that she calls “the optics of optimism.” This strategy first attempts to meet Bayle head-on by denying his first two assertions. That is, optimists hold that there is far more joy in life than suffering and that we have significant capacity to choose happiness over sorrow. In this dispute, disagreement centers around a thought experiment proposed by Bayle: if you ask those advanced in years whether or not they would willingly pass through their lives again, with the same ration of good and evil, most will answer negatively. Optimists, such as William King and Leibniz, disagree. As they see it, most people would readily agree to live their lives again, if the alternative was oblivion.The problem for the optimists here is not that their answer is implausible. Indeed, they seem to be correct about the general opinion of humanity. It is, rather, that it is insufficient for their purposes. For although Bayle may indeed be wrong that most people would choose oblivion over a second pass through life, the existence of even one creature who would reasonably choose oblivion is enough to trouble those who assert the existence of a good universal order. This is where the optics of optimism come in. For, when confronted with the likely existence of even one miserable wretch, the optimists shift their arguments from the “creaturely” to the “cosmic” perspective (71). The world, they concede, is not unblemished by miserable wretches, but their suffering is either necessary for the overall good order or more than adequately rewarded in the next life.At this point, according to Van Der Lugt, the structure of the debate about the problem of evil in the early modern era is set. The pessimists, following Bayle, find the optimists’ attempts at rational theodicy cruelly dismissive of actually experienced suffering. At the same time, the optimists believe the pessimists overstate their case and consequently cause unnecessary suffering by promoting a gloomy view of existence. As Van Der Lugt notes, both of these positions are deeply ethical; they both care about the practical effects of philosophical and theological attempts to address the problem of evil. And in the second section of Dark Matters she takes us on a “Grand Tour” through the ways this debate played out during the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries (105).This section of the book, like any grand tour, is necessarily selective. Major stops include Voltaire (chapter 3), La Mettrie and Maupertuis (chapter 4), Hume (chapter 5), Rousseau (chapter 6), Kant (chapter 7), and Schopenhauer (chapter 8). As the subtle interplay among these figures resists easy summary, I will not attempt a synopsis here but rather make two general comments. First, in this section of the book, Van Der Lugt skillfully demonstrates the contributions of these figures without becoming distracted by thorny interpretive issues. And second, the overall impression given by this long section of Dark Matters is that the “debate” between pessimists and optimists in the early modern period is less a debate than a collaboration. Certainly Maupertuis disagreed with La Mettrie, Hume with the Stoics, Rousseau with Voltaire, Kant and Schopenhauer with everyone. But these disagreements were the effect of a deeper agreement about the importance of offering hope and consolation to those who suffer. The true problem of evil that emerges from these chapters is that philosophy is insufficient to the task. Perhaps we can rationally explain the origin of evil; perhaps we can justify the existence of all suffering as deserved or necessary. But even if the optimists are correct, theodicy does little to address the lived experience of suffering and sorrow. Rational inquiry is, therefore, not the end but the beginning of an answer the problem of evil. It can show us where sympathy, consolation, and hope are necessary, but it cannot provide them on its own.This concern with the ethical import of the problem of evil and the use and limitations of philosophy in the face of suffering also informs the last section, and chapter, of Dark Matters. Subtitled “Pessimism as a Moral Source,” this chapter aims to apply the lessons of the foregoing to the present (395). According to Van Der Lugt, this task is urgent for two reasons. First, Van Der Lugt is wary of the contemporary gospel of self-actualization. There is a dark side to being told that you can be anything if you just work hard enough: “If we’re not happy, we are doing something wrong” (402). Second, in addition to the ubiquity of debased aphoristic Stoicism, Van Der Lugt worries that our increasing exposure to depictions of suffering, as supplied by the internet and mass media, depletes our capacity for sympathy. There is an obvious moral difference between torturing someone to death and fictionally depicting the act of torturing someone to death. But it seems likely, Van Der Lugt proposes, that from the perspective of the spectator, the deleterious effects of watching these depictions for entertainment is similar.Thus, according to Van Der Lugt, we find in the Baylean tradition of pessimism and the debate that followed not only an overlooked and fascinating philosophical tradition but also a necessary corrective. For pessimism at its best is not a prediction that things will turn out ill. It is, rather, a reminder of the fragility of life, and the importance of sympathy, consolation, and hope.As an intellectual history, Dark Matters is superb. Throughout, Van Der Lugt traces the tradition of pessimism during the early modern period with clarity, energy, and subtlety. Subject experts on the philosophers profiled may complain that Van Der Lugt rarely gives her opinion regarding contested interpretations, but Van Der Lugt is relentlessly unconcerned with these issues. The story of Dark Matters is the story of pessimism and optimism after Bayle, and so it is of little importance, for instance, whether Kant ultimately decided that theodicy is or is not impossible. Similarly, some may complain that important figures have been left out of the narrative. Yet, as Van Der Lugt notes, the intellectual history contained in Dark Matters is not intended to be exhaustive (396). The point of the work is to rehabilitate pessimism as a moral stance, not to comprehensively document every position that could be called pessimistic or optimistic.Finally, some may find her willingness to drop the facade of philosophical distance in the last chapter unseemly. Is certainly unconventional, but this reader appreciated her willingness to take the risk. Further, the practical turn is justified by the preceding argument. To treat value-oriented pessimism as a mere mental exercise would betray the very tradition Dark Matters wishes to revive.Thus, with respect to the focus, selectivity, and practical orientation of the book, Van Der Lugt’s decisions are all justifiable. Yet they come at a cost, as well. For my part, the most troublesome was the first, which seemed to occasionally rob the reader of informed insight. For instance, near the end of her chapter on Schopenhauer, Van Der Lugt writes, “Whether [Schopenhauer’s argument against suicide] works is another question: my point is merely that the structure of Schopenhauer’s response seems to get something right” (383). It is understandable that Van Der Lugt would not want to weigh in here and broach inessential subjects. Yet having come so far with so competent a guide, both here and at other points, I could not help but be disappointed she did not venture an opinion.Stylistically, the book is not only well written but is leavened with humor and humanity. Given the subject matter, these attributes are both helpful and necessary. In the hands of a lesser author, discussions of, for example, philosophical justifications for suicide could be oppressive, not to mention dangerous. Yet Van Der Lugt manages them with care and compassion, without sacrificing philosophical rigor. In sum, Dark Matters is a major contribution to the understanding the oft-overlooked tradition of value-oriented pessimism. Whether it will ultimately spur further interest in this tradition, or the way this tradition is manifested in the philosophers profiled, one cannot say. As Van Der Lugt notes, philosophical fashion is unpredictable (105). Yet it is surely an informative and, surprisingly, enjoyable work, one that throws considerable light on the shadow side of human existence.","PeriodicalId":48129,"journal":{"name":"PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW","volume":"32 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":2.8000,"publicationDate":"2023-07-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":"0","resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.1215/00318108-10469577","RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"0","JCRName":"PHILOSOPHY","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Abstract
In Dark Matters, Mara Van Der Lugt attempts to rehabilitate pessimism as a moral stance. Critical to this task is the distinction between what she calls “future-oriented” and “value-oriented” pessimism (10). The former is what most people presently understand the word pessimism to mean: a gloomy view about the future, an attitude of premature defeat.Although this kind of fatalism can be found alongside value-oriented pessimism, Van Der Lugt is chiefly interested in the latter, which she portrays as a sympathetic appreciation of suffering that, although not without hope, does not attempt to explain—let alone explain away—the existence of evil.To make this case, Dark Matters proceeds in three sections. The first section, comprising the introduction and first two chapters of the book, sets up the contrast between future- and value-oriented pessimism by examining various approaches to the classic problem of evil, as summarized by Epicurus’s classic trilemma among God’s power, God’s goodness, and the existence of evil.Some of these are what she calls “negative” strategies, which deny the premise that there is evil—or, more generously, a problematic amount of evil—in the world (33). And some are “positive” strategies, which accept the premise of evil in the world but attempt to explain the origin of evil by, for example, casting it as the inevitable side effect of free will and/or sin (35). Whatever their views about the future, those who take up these strategies are, in Van Der Lugt’s terms, “optimists.” And they are so by virtue of believing the problem of evil can be satisfactorily answered.On the other hand, those who take the contrasting approach, believing that the problem of evil is so acute that it cannot be rationally resolved, are pessimists. And first among them, for Van Der Lugt’s purposes, is Pierre Bayle, who set the terms of the pessimist/optimist debate in the early modern era by making the problem of evil primarily a problem of suffering.For Bayle, the primary task of addressing Epicurus’s query is not to justify or undermine belief in the existence of a good God. It is, rather, to understand, or at least appreciate, the irrefutable experience of human suffering. This focus on suffering alone does not make Bayle a pessimist. Rather, what makes him a pessimist is his insistence that there is far more suffering than pleasure in life, that we have little power to choose whether we suffer or flourish in any given circumstance, and that most of our pains cannot be explained as just punishment.In opposing Bayle’s diagnosis, Van Der Lugt suggests that most optimists employ a rhetorical strategy that she calls “the optics of optimism.” This strategy first attempts to meet Bayle head-on by denying his first two assertions. That is, optimists hold that there is far more joy in life than suffering and that we have significant capacity to choose happiness over sorrow. In this dispute, disagreement centers around a thought experiment proposed by Bayle: if you ask those advanced in years whether or not they would willingly pass through their lives again, with the same ration of good and evil, most will answer negatively. Optimists, such as William King and Leibniz, disagree. As they see it, most people would readily agree to live their lives again, if the alternative was oblivion.The problem for the optimists here is not that their answer is implausible. Indeed, they seem to be correct about the general opinion of humanity. It is, rather, that it is insufficient for their purposes. For although Bayle may indeed be wrong that most people would choose oblivion over a second pass through life, the existence of even one creature who would reasonably choose oblivion is enough to trouble those who assert the existence of a good universal order. This is where the optics of optimism come in. For, when confronted with the likely existence of even one miserable wretch, the optimists shift their arguments from the “creaturely” to the “cosmic” perspective (71). The world, they concede, is not unblemished by miserable wretches, but their suffering is either necessary for the overall good order or more than adequately rewarded in the next life.At this point, according to Van Der Lugt, the structure of the debate about the problem of evil in the early modern era is set. The pessimists, following Bayle, find the optimists’ attempts at rational theodicy cruelly dismissive of actually experienced suffering. At the same time, the optimists believe the pessimists overstate their case and consequently cause unnecessary suffering by promoting a gloomy view of existence. As Van Der Lugt notes, both of these positions are deeply ethical; they both care about the practical effects of philosophical and theological attempts to address the problem of evil. And in the second section of Dark Matters she takes us on a “Grand Tour” through the ways this debate played out during the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries (105).This section of the book, like any grand tour, is necessarily selective. Major stops include Voltaire (chapter 3), La Mettrie and Maupertuis (chapter 4), Hume (chapter 5), Rousseau (chapter 6), Kant (chapter 7), and Schopenhauer (chapter 8). As the subtle interplay among these figures resists easy summary, I will not attempt a synopsis here but rather make two general comments. First, in this section of the book, Van Der Lugt skillfully demonstrates the contributions of these figures without becoming distracted by thorny interpretive issues. And second, the overall impression given by this long section of Dark Matters is that the “debate” between pessimists and optimists in the early modern period is less a debate than a collaboration. Certainly Maupertuis disagreed with La Mettrie, Hume with the Stoics, Rousseau with Voltaire, Kant and Schopenhauer with everyone. But these disagreements were the effect of a deeper agreement about the importance of offering hope and consolation to those who suffer. The true problem of evil that emerges from these chapters is that philosophy is insufficient to the task. Perhaps we can rationally explain the origin of evil; perhaps we can justify the existence of all suffering as deserved or necessary. But even if the optimists are correct, theodicy does little to address the lived experience of suffering and sorrow. Rational inquiry is, therefore, not the end but the beginning of an answer the problem of evil. It can show us where sympathy, consolation, and hope are necessary, but it cannot provide them on its own.This concern with the ethical import of the problem of evil and the use and limitations of philosophy in the face of suffering also informs the last section, and chapter, of Dark Matters. Subtitled “Pessimism as a Moral Source,” this chapter aims to apply the lessons of the foregoing to the present (395). According to Van Der Lugt, this task is urgent for two reasons. First, Van Der Lugt is wary of the contemporary gospel of self-actualization. There is a dark side to being told that you can be anything if you just work hard enough: “If we’re not happy, we are doing something wrong” (402). Second, in addition to the ubiquity of debased aphoristic Stoicism, Van Der Lugt worries that our increasing exposure to depictions of suffering, as supplied by the internet and mass media, depletes our capacity for sympathy. There is an obvious moral difference between torturing someone to death and fictionally depicting the act of torturing someone to death. But it seems likely, Van Der Lugt proposes, that from the perspective of the spectator, the deleterious effects of watching these depictions for entertainment is similar.Thus, according to Van Der Lugt, we find in the Baylean tradition of pessimism and the debate that followed not only an overlooked and fascinating philosophical tradition but also a necessary corrective. For pessimism at its best is not a prediction that things will turn out ill. It is, rather, a reminder of the fragility of life, and the importance of sympathy, consolation, and hope.As an intellectual history, Dark Matters is superb. Throughout, Van Der Lugt traces the tradition of pessimism during the early modern period with clarity, energy, and subtlety. Subject experts on the philosophers profiled may complain that Van Der Lugt rarely gives her opinion regarding contested interpretations, but Van Der Lugt is relentlessly unconcerned with these issues. The story of Dark Matters is the story of pessimism and optimism after Bayle, and so it is of little importance, for instance, whether Kant ultimately decided that theodicy is or is not impossible. Similarly, some may complain that important figures have been left out of the narrative. Yet, as Van Der Lugt notes, the intellectual history contained in Dark Matters is not intended to be exhaustive (396). The point of the work is to rehabilitate pessimism as a moral stance, not to comprehensively document every position that could be called pessimistic or optimistic.Finally, some may find her willingness to drop the facade of philosophical distance in the last chapter unseemly. Is certainly unconventional, but this reader appreciated her willingness to take the risk. Further, the practical turn is justified by the preceding argument. To treat value-oriented pessimism as a mere mental exercise would betray the very tradition Dark Matters wishes to revive.Thus, with respect to the focus, selectivity, and practical orientation of the book, Van Der Lugt’s decisions are all justifiable. Yet they come at a cost, as well. For my part, the most troublesome was the first, which seemed to occasionally rob the reader of informed insight. For instance, near the end of her chapter on Schopenhauer, Van Der Lugt writes, “Whether [Schopenhauer’s argument against suicide] works is another question: my point is merely that the structure of Schopenhauer’s response seems to get something right” (383). It is understandable that Van Der Lugt would not want to weigh in here and broach inessential subjects. Yet having come so far with so competent a guide, both here and at other points, I could not help but be disappointed she did not venture an opinion.Stylistically, the book is not only well written but is leavened with humor and humanity. Given the subject matter, these attributes are both helpful and necessary. In the hands of a lesser author, discussions of, for example, philosophical justifications for suicide could be oppressive, not to mention dangerous. Yet Van Der Lugt manages them with care and compassion, without sacrificing philosophical rigor. In sum, Dark Matters is a major contribution to the understanding the oft-overlooked tradition of value-oriented pessimism. Whether it will ultimately spur further interest in this tradition, or the way this tradition is manifested in the philosophers profiled, one cannot say. As Van Der Lugt notes, philosophical fashion is unpredictable (105). Yet it is surely an informative and, surprisingly, enjoyable work, one that throws considerable light on the shadow side of human existence.
在《暗物质》一书中,玛拉·范德卢特试图恢复悲观主义的道德立场。这项任务的关键在于区分她所说的“面向未来”和“面向价值”的悲观主义(10)。前者是目前大多数人对悲观一词的理解:对未来的悲观看法,过早失败的态度。虽然这种宿命论可以与价值导向的悲观主义并存,但范德卢特主要对后者感兴趣,她将后者描绘为对苦难的同情欣赏,尽管并非没有希望,但并不试图解释——更不用说解释了——邪恶的存在。为了证明这一点,《暗物质》分为三个部分。第一部分,包括本书的引言和前两章,通过考察对恶的经典问题的各种方法,建立了以未来为导向和以价值为导向的悲观主义之间的对比,伊壁鸠鲁的经典三困境总结了上帝的力量,上帝的善良和邪恶的存在。其中一些是她所谓的“消极”策略,这些策略否认世界上存在邪恶——或者更慷慨地说,邪恶的数量有问题——的前提(33)。还有一些是“积极”策略,它们接受世界上存在邪恶的前提,但试图解释邪恶的起源,例如,将其视为自由意志和/或罪恶不可避免的副作用(35)。无论他们对未来的看法如何,那些采取这些策略的人,用范德卢格特的话来说,都是“乐观主义者”。他们相信邪恶的问题可以得到令人满意的回答。另一方面,那些持相反观点的人是悲观主义者,他们认为邪恶的问题是如此尖锐,以至于无法理性地解决。首先,根据范德卢格特的目的,是皮埃尔·贝利,他在现代早期设定了悲观主义者和乐观主义者的争论,他把邪恶的问题主要看作是苦难的问题。对于Bayle来说,解决伊壁鸠鲁问题的首要任务不是证明或破坏对善神存在的信仰。更确切地说,是理解,或者至少是欣赏,人类痛苦的无可辩驳的经验。仅仅关注苦难并不能使贝尔成为悲观主义者。相反,使他成为悲观主义者的是他坚持认为生活中的痛苦远比快乐要多,我们几乎没有能力选择在任何特定的情况下是受苦还是繁荣,我们的大多数痛苦不能被解释为仅仅是惩罚。在反对Bayle的诊断时,Van Der Lugt认为大多数乐观主义者采用了一种修辞策略,她称之为“乐观主义的光学”。这一策略首先试图通过否定贝尔的前两个主张来正面对抗他。也就是说,乐观主义者认为生活中的快乐远远多于痛苦,我们有很大的能力选择快乐而不是悲伤。在这场争论中,分歧集中在Bayle提出的一个思想实验上:如果你问那些上了年纪的人,他们是否愿意以同样的善恶比例再过一次他们的生活,大多数人会给出否定的答案。乐观主义者,如威廉·金和莱布尼茨,不同意。在他们看来,如果另一种选择是被遗忘,大多数人会欣然同意重新过他们的生活。对于乐观主义者来说,问题不在于他们的答案不可信。事实上,他们对人类的普遍看法似乎是正确的。更确切地说,这不足以达到他们的目的。因为,尽管贝勒认为大多数人会选择遗忘而不是生命中的第二次轮回的观点可能确实是错误的,但即使有一种生物会合理地选择遗忘,也足以让那些主张存在良好的普遍秩序的人感到不安。这就是乐观主义发挥作用的地方。因为,当面对一个可能存在的可怜虫时,乐观主义者将他们的论点从“受造物”转向“宇宙”的观点(71)。他们承认,这个世界并不是没有被悲惨的可怜虫玷污的,但他们的痛苦要么是整体良好秩序所必需的,要么是在来生得到足够的回报。在这一点上,根据Van Der Lugt,关于早期现代邪恶问题的辩论结构已经确定。悲观主义者追随Bayle,发现乐观主义者对理性神正论的尝试是对实际经历的痛苦的残酷蔑视。与此同时,乐观主义者认为悲观主义者夸大了他们的情况,从而通过宣扬一种悲观的存在观而造成不必要的痛苦。正如范德卢格特所指出的,这两种立场都具有深刻的伦理意义;他们都关心哲学和神学试图解决邪恶问题的实际效果。在《暗物质》的第二部分,她带我们进行了一次“大旅行”,穿越了这场辩论在18世纪和19世纪的演变过程。
期刊介绍:
In continuous publication since 1892, the Philosophical Review has a long-standing reputation for excellence and has published many papers now considered classics in the field, such as W. V. O. Quine"s “Two Dogmas of Empiricism,” Thomas Nagel"s “What Is It Like to Be a Bat?” and the early work of John Rawls. The journal aims to publish original scholarly work in all areas of analytic philosophy, with an emphasis on material of general interest to academic philosophers, and is one of the few journals in the discipline to publish book reviews.