Bad Question!

IF 3.3 1区 哲学 Q1 ETHICS
Sam Berstler
{"title":"Bad Question!","authors":"Sam Berstler","doi":"10.1111/papa.12249","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"Individuals…exude expressions.1 Performers can stop giving expressions but cannot stop giving them off.2 Defense attorney Mickey Haller (and protagonist of the fictional series Lincoln Lawyer) has his witness exactly where he wants him.3 Anton Shavar isn't on trial. But Haller wants to insinuate that Shavar committed the murders that Haller's client stands accused of committing. First, he needs to insinuate that Shavar knows how to orchestrate a hit. Haller asks about Shavar's former job: “I have a background in formal intelligence in Israel.” So he was in the Mossad? Shavar replies: “I did not say that.” Haller repeats the question: “Were you in the Mossad? An organization which is known to carry out targeted assassinations?” The prosecution objects. Then a man at the back of the court room stands up. He announces that he is Mr. Shavar's counsel and that “Mr. Shavar's past employment in Israel, whatever it may be, has no bearing on this case. It could jeopardize the national security of one of this country's closest allies.” Haller smirks. Bingo. “It's all right, Your Honor, I'll take that as a yes.” Just by asking, “Were you in the Mossad?” Haller had trapped Shavar. All of his available options became bad. Shavar could tell the truth, but the cost would be too high. Shavar knew that Haller would use this information to smear his good name. Shavar could lie, but the risk would be too high: under oath, to lie is to commit a felony offense. Or he could stay silent. But that too was a bad choice. That Shavar stayed silent revealed that Shavar had good reason to stay silent. And, as Haller's quip “I'll take that as a yes” dramatized, Shavar thereby revealed that he worked for Mossad.4 Courtrooms have elaborate rules to attempt to defuse what I call the problem of loud silence. In Lincoln Lawyer, the judge instructs the jury to disregard Haller's final quip. If the jury does what it should, it will deliberate without taking into account the information that Haller extracted through Shavar's silence. But without formal rules of evidence and deliberation, everyday interactions offer no such kindness. The right sort of question put to us, in the right sort of way, can leave us with only three bad options: to lie; to speak truthfully and reveal what we do not want to reveal; and to stay silent and reveal what we do not want to reveal anyway. I call this the problem of loud silence. The right sort of question, put the right sort of way, can do worse still. A tell-tale pause, a barely perceptible facial expression, a subtle vocal change, an odd word choice: all have the potential to reveal sensitive information. You might ask me a prying question, not because you want to know what I will say but because you want to see how I will react. Face-to-face conversation, then, renders us uniquely informationally vulnerable to each other. We are porous beings, our information often escapes from us against our will, and we can exploit this vulnerability in order to extract information from each other. Against a sufficiently powerful mind control machine, I am defenseless, and there is nothing I can do to improve my defenses. But against prying questions, I can martial some protection, and I can improve that protection over time. As any good poker player knows, the more I learn to bring my “tells” under voluntary control, that is, the more that I learn to manage the information that I both voluntarily and non-voluntarily exude, the less vulnerable I become to your questions. Drawing from the work of mid-century sociologist Goffman,5 I call this latter capacity poise. In the arms race between those who would pry and those who would have poise, what safeguards does morality offer? In particular, when is a prying question not just boorish, uncouth, or obnoxious but genuinely wrongful? And even more particularly, when does a prying question not just wrong but wrong because it violates the addressee's privacy rights? In other words, when does an intrusive question not just offend but intrude? I propose two different principles. (I remain neutral on which one is correct.) The first principle: if p is my private information, then I have a right against you asking me p? iff, in asking me p?, you thereby undermine my effective control over whether, when, and how to reveal p to you. The second principle: if p is my private information, then I have a right against you asking me p? iff you could reasonably expect that in asking me p?, you would thereby undermine my effective control over whether, when, and how to reveal p to you. (This is an approximation, actually. There are some book-keeping issues I consider later.) These principles say that you may not ask me questions about private matters that also force private information out of me. I can force information from you even if I do not coerce you to answer my question. Compare two ways that I can force you to remain seated. I can say, “Sit there, or I'll shoot.” That's coercion. Or I can press my hand onto your shoulder, so that you cannot physically rise. Interestingly, we do not have a general right against prying questions. If you ask me a question about where I would like to eat and you thereby force information out of me, you have not violated any of my rights. I will assume, at the outset, that our intuitions are right. Bad questions do violate our privacy rights. The question is: how could this be possible? Some “conversational libertarians” will not like this starting point.6 Conversational libertarians think that bad questions can be tacky or boorish. But they do not think that bad questions can be wrongful, or at least, not wrongful because they are rights violating. I ask for such readers' patience. My analysis of why bad questions violate our privacy rights also constitutes an argument that they do. I also assume, at the outset, that we do have a class of rights that deserve the name privacy rights. These privacy rights function to protect “my” information. My medical diagnoses, sexual history, and religious background, but not the identity of the university at which I work, are “my” information in this special sense. We have a special and legitimate interest in maintaining a kind of discretionary control over to whom, when, whether, and how to reveal “our” information. This interest, in turn, grounds and justifies our privacy rights.7 And this interest may be grounded in or explained or justified by a more basic interest or capacity still. This vision has its skeptics. Famously, Thomson points out that many of the paradigmatic “privacy violations” are also other sorts of rights violations.8 If I break into your laptop to read your love letters to Justin Bieber, I may have violated your privacy rights, but I have definitely violated your property rights. If a man on the subway pulls my skirt down, he may have violated my privacy rights, but he's definitely violated my right against bodily trespass. If that's correct, then what work is there left for privacy rights to do? Unlike the privacy violations that typically exercise moral philosophers, bad questions do not seem to violate any rights beyond my privacy rights. For the privacy skeptic, then, one take-away from my paper is that privacy rights have some real work to do after all. I have arranged this paper in the following way. In the next section, I will raise a skeptical challenge for myself and for White's recent discussion of prying questions.9 Though prying questions might express disrespect or entitlement (the challenge goes), surely they are not rights violations. A question like, “Do you have cancer?” is better analogized to a clueless or entitled request for a favor, not to peeping through a curtain. In order to respond to the worry, in Section III, I introduce three key concepts, each inspired by the work of Goffman: informational self-control; poise; and mentalism. In the fourth section, I use these concepts to defend what I call the Bad Question Principle. I suggest that the Bad Question Principle flows from the same interests that ground our privacy rights and show why the preceding discussion should convince even the privacy skeptic that we have privacy rights. Then I distinguish two different interpretations of the BQP and draw out the consequences of each interpretation. In the final section, I tease out some further questions that my analysis raises. I ask how far our rights against prying-like behavior extend. I argue it is sometimes permissible to ask via email what we cannot ask face-to-face. I show that my discussion may reveal an unexpected function of certain politeness norms, which may in turn ground (some of) their value. And I close by considering the value of our porousness, specifically in response to questions. Our imperfect control over our poise is central, I suggest, not just for our capacity to project authenticity but also to our capacity to engage in certain kinds of politeness strategies. Camila is suffering from early stage cancer. She is a private person, however, and she isn't ready to tell her coworkers. She especially isn't ready to tell Jacqueline, the departmental busybody. Unfortunately, Jacqueline has noticed that Camila has been looking sicker and sicker; that she has been taking time off work; and that she often cries in the bathroom. And, like many busybodies, Jacqueline just has a knack for knowing what's wrong with others. Jacqueline stops by Camila's office and asks, out of the blue, “Do you have cancer?” Compare this all to the way we might describe merely boorish, obnoxious, and out-of-touch requests. Suppose that my undergraduate student, Tommy, asks me, for no particularly good reason, “Can you read and return this draft to me in an hour?”11 The request would irritate me. It may even anger me. I'd ask myself, “Who does Tommy think he is?” I'd wonder why Tommy feels so entitled to my time or where he found the chutzpah to ask this. For all that, I would not accuse Tommy of prying, probing, putting me under a microscope, or otherwise violating my rights. His request might have expressed something morally objectionable, but it did not expose me. Say that a question is expressively problematic iff, in asking it, the speaker expresses something morally objectionable. Tommy's request is expressively problematic because it expresses a kind of entitlement to my time. Say that a question pries or intrudes iff, in asking it, the speaker violates the addressee's privacy rights. Jacqueline's question may be expressively problematic, and expressively problematic questions may or may not wrong, some or all of the time. But if expressively problematic questions (per se) wrong at all, they wrong in virtue of what they communicate.12 Here I am not interested in what Jacqueline's question communicates or whether requests can wrong because of what they communicate. I am interested in why (it seems that) Jacqueline's question wrongs because it intrudes.13 Consider this analogy. You ask me, out of the blue, “Hey, can I borrow your blender?” Let's stipulate that this is genuinely a request, not a threat in disguise. The question, “Hey, can I borrow your blender?” is really the question, “Will you waive your property rights with respect to me and your blender?” Similarly, (you might reasonably think) the question, “Do you have cancer?” is really the question, “Will you waive your privacy rights with respect to me and the matter of whether you have cancer?” A request to waive a right R might be expressively problematic. It might even be wrongfully expressively problematic. But an expressively problematic request to waive a right R doesn't constitute a violation of R itself.14 Here's one disanalogy between the question, “Hey, can I borrow your blender?” and Jacqueline's question, “Do you have a cancer?” which (following White) I've built into the case itself. If you ask me, “Will you waive your property rights with respect to me and your blender?” I can tell you, “No,” and that will be the end of it. If Jacqueline were to ask Camila, “Will you waive your privacy rights with respect to me and the matter of whether you have cancer?” and Camila says, “No,” then Jacqueline may in fact get what she wants. For sometimes, to decline to waive one's privacy rights—whether by saying, “It's none of your business,” or “I won't answer,” or pointedly changing the subject—just is to give away one's private information. Following White, let's build some stipulations into the case.15 Camila finds herself with three options. She can tell Jacqueline the truth and so reveal what she does not want to reveal. She can stay silent and again reveal what she does not want to reveal. Or she can lie. Camila is staring down the same gun as Shavar. In other words, Jacqueline has created a loud silence problem for Camila. The question I will now investigate is this: just in virtue of creating a loud silence problem for Camila, has Jacqueline violated Camila's privacy rights? In other words: can we use the nature of loud silence problems to vindicate our intuition that Jacqueline has violated Camila's privacy rights? I will temporarily answer, “Yes,” and do my best to develop this line of response. I will ultimately reject it as misguided, but the errors will prove instructive for what's to come. Before doing this, let me add a few clarificatory remarks. Until now, I've described speakers as “staying silent” in response to a question. When describing courtrooms, that makes sense. On the stand, we can plead the fifth. Our attorney can object. In real speech situations, we rarely “stay silent” by literally staying silent. To use a term from H.P. Grice, say that a speaker who is “staying silent” in my sense opts out.16 We can opt out of conversations altogether or opt out of a conversation's subcomponents. I might say, “Sorry, kid, I'm busy,” to make clear that I'm not interested in conversing with you at all. When I opt out of a question you have posed to me, I make clear that I'm not interested in providing you an answer or, if I do not know the answer, telling you that I do not know the answer. (But note that a curt “Sorry, don't know”—delivered to the suspicious person who has just approached you, before she has said much of anything—can constitute an opt-out move.) Opt outs can range from the straightforward, “I'd rather not answer that,” to the facetious, “What lovely weather we're having,” to the disapproving, “I didn't hear you say that.” Once I responded to an obnoxious, out-of-the-blue question, “Are you carrying student loan debt? How much?” with a terse, “How much do you weigh?” Say that when a speaker faces a loud silence problem, she is in a context in which her decision to opt out of the question p? or the conversation altogether would significantly and justifiably raise or lower her interlocutor's credence that p.17 “Significantly” is a weasel word. I use it to emphasize that our silence can be problematically “loud” even when it licenses only very secure suspicions. But for the sake of simplicity, I will just focus on cases in which opting out generates knowledge. Say also that a speaker who asks p? induces a loud silence context when her act makes it the case that her interlocutor faces a loud silence problem. We can induce loud silence contexts intentionally and unintentionally. The claim under consideration is not the claim that whenever I ask someone p? and so induce a loud silence context for her, I thereby wrong her. If this were the claim, then we could—quite easily, without reaching for recherché scenarios—generate an overwhelming number of apparent counter-examples. I might ask my co-teacher, “Do you really like the Twilight movies?” and create a loud silence context of him. In fact, I did this recently, as banter, and I do not think that either of us think that I wronged him. Danny is my undergraduate student, and he's working with me on his senior thesis. I suspect that things aren't going well for Danny, and he's embarrassed about it. I also know that when things aren't going well for Danny, he never wants to tell me about it. When Danny walks into my office, I ask him, “How is the senior thesis going?” When we intentionally create loud silence contexts, (you might think), we undermine our interlocutors' capacity to choose whether or not to reveal some information to us. Since I do not have a right that you refrain from putting me in loud silence contexts, I do not have a right that you refrain from undermining my capacity to choose whether or not to reveal information to you. If this sounds like an uncomfortable conclusion, I think it is only because it is easy to confuse this claim with a related one. I have a right that you refrain from undermining my capacity to choose whether to tell you some information. You may not coerce me into telling you something, because, as a general matter, you may not coerce me to do anything. The difference is that tellings are always actions that I intentionally perform, whereas revealings needn't be. When I opt out in a loud silence context, I reveal something to you only in the sense that my action provides you with certain kinds of evidence. The claim under consideration is more restricted: whenever I ask someone p? and so induce a loud silence context for her with respect to her private information, I thereby wrong her. This proposal meshes with the intuitive thought that morality provides us special safeguards over “sensitive” information. In what sense does the bad questioner undermine her victim's control over her private information? Here's a first pass thought. Before Jacqueline said anything, Camila could permissibly choose to reveal her diagnosis to Jacqueline, and she could permissibly choose to keep it to herself. After Jacqueline asks her question, Camila cannot permissibly keep the information to herself, because she cannot permissibly lie to Jacqueline. (Bear with me on this assumption.) Camila has lost normative control over whether or not to reveal her diagnosis. And Camila lost this control because Jacqueline deliberately conspired to constrain Camila's permissible option set in just this way. Here's an analogy. Suppose Camila lives in an isolated house on a mountain road. Jacqueline is desperate to see the inside of Camila's living room. But Camila, who is shy and not a fan of Jacqueline, refuses to invite Jacqueline into her home. So Jacqueline concocts an elaborate and desperate plan. During a snowstorm, Jacqueline goes hiking in the woods near Camila's house. Jacqueline wears inadequate winter gear and doesn't bring a phone. Jacqueline intentionally brings herself near hypothermic death. She then walks to Camila's house, rings the doorbell, and begs for Camila to let her into her house. It seems to me that Camila is obligated to permit Jacqueline to enter her house. (And if Camila doesn't voluntarily invite Jacqueline in, it seems that Jacqueline can permissibly force her way indoors to save her life.) In carrying out this manipulative scheme, Jacqueline deliberately conspires to undermine Camila's normative control over her property. In entering Camila's house, Jacqueline does not violate Camila's privacy rights, at least not in the traditional sense. (Even if she forces her way inside, Jacqueline at best infringes them.) But Jacqueline's manipulative scheme clearly fails to respect Camila's underlying and legitimate interest in maintaining certain kinds of control over who enters her home and when. Similarly, Jacqueline's bad question might not violate Camila's privacy rights in the traditional sense. But her bad question is its own kind of manipulative scheme, which likewise fails to respect the interests that ultimately ground Camila's privacy rights. Unfortunately, this kind of account stumbles early on. For Camila loses normative control in the relevant respect only if Camila cannot permissibly lie to Jacqueline about her diagnosis. This assumption is, at best, dubious. First, it just seems plainly clear that in response to and because of Jacqueline's inappropriate question, Camila can lie to Jacqueline. If Camila did lie to Jacqueline, Jacqueline would not have a legitimate complaint against Camila. Jacqueline would have no one to blame but herself. And if you were Camila's friend, and if Camila were fretting to you about whether to lie or not in such a situation, you'd almost certainly counsel her, “Jacqueline, in putting that question to you, gave up her right to a good faith reply.” Even a stringent moralist like Kant, in his Lectures on Evil, acknowledges that “if I cannot save myself by maintaining my silence, then my lie is a weapon of defence.”19 For otherwise, “we might often become victims of the wickedness of others who were ready to abuse our truthfulness.”20 White likewise observes, “If dodging the question or refusing to answer would allow [Jacqueline] to deduce her secret, she may lie…That the lie is permissible and the question impermissible is clearly no coincidence.”21 There is more to say in favor of this viewpoint. In the hypothermia scheme, Jacqueline manipulates the situation in order to dramatically change her underlying interest in accessing Camila's house: her life depends upon it. If Jacqueline doesn't gain access to her house, she will die. In the bad question scheme, Jaqueline's question doesn't change the nature or urgency of her interest in learning Camila's diagnosis. If Camila were to respond with the lie, “I don't have cancer,” her lie would not set Jacqueline's interests back any more than would her out-of-the-blue assertion, “I don't have cancer.” This is not to say that these lies don't set Jacqueline's interests back. Jacqueline, like all agents, has an interest in gaining knowledge and avoiding false beliefs, and lies undermine that interest. But given Jacqueline intentionally conspired to bring her interest in avoiding false beliefs into conflict with Camila's interest in protecting her privacy and given that her underlying interests have otherwise not changed, it would seem perverse for morality to decide in Jacqueline's favor. Here's a last-ditch effort to save the normative control explanation. Let us concede that it is permissible for Camila to lie to Jacqueline, and it is permissible in part or in whole because Jacqueline intentionally asked Camila a question that created a loud silence context about her private information. Still, you might think, Jacqueline conspired to create a situation in which Camila infringed Jacqueline's rights—justifiably so, of course, but an infringement, nonetheless. And as infringements sometimes do, that might leave a residue. Camila might owe Jacqueline some kind of “compensation”—perhaps an apology, if Jacqueline ever learns the truth, for example, or more metaphorical compensation, in the form of a pang of conscience or regret. Still, even if we concede this point, could this plausibly explain the facts that we aim to vindicate? In creating a situation in which Camila has no reasonable choice but to infringe Jacqueline's right against deception, has Jacqueline thereby violated Camila's privacy? To compel me to infringe your right R in order to protect my right R* does not seem to thereby violate my right R* or even to disrespect the interests that ground my right R*. It is rather to disrespect my interest in not infringing your rights. We have been investigating a certain analysis of prying question, one on which Jacqueline intrudes insofar as she intentionally undermines Camila's normative control over the disclosure of her private information. That analysis has floundered on a difficult-to-defend presupposition. If this isn't the correct story about why Jacqueline's question intrudes, what is? The problem, I will argue, is that we have misunderstood the sense in which Camila can't conceal her information from Jacqueline. It's not that Camila cannot permissibly conceal her information from Jacqueline. Rather, Camila cannot conceal her information from Jacqueline in a more flat-footed sense. She is not able to do so. She lacks the skill it would require. Jacqueline has undermined Camila's effective control over her private information and, in doing so, has wronged her. Or so I will argue in Section IV. In this section, I will set the stage for that argument. Here I introduce a more realistic vision of conversation. Face-to-face conversations occur rapidly, between flesh-and-blood people staring into each other's eyes, with only imperfect access to their knowledge and imperfect self-control, and with an extraordinary capacity for mind-reading. Given this, conversation renders us uniquely vulnerable to each other. Ask me just the right questions, in just the right way, and you can turn me into an open book—without inducing a loud silence context at all. To describe these vulnerabilities with greater precision, I will also introduce a suite of new terminology, grounded in the work of Goffman. But first, I want to introduce a real-life Camila, an anonymous woman who wrote into an advice column a few years ago. To make it easy to refer to her, I'm going to call her Rose. By studying the advice columnist's reply and Rose's overall predicament, I will argue that loud silence contexts are much more fraught and interesting than the previous discussion suggests. On behalf of all new moms, please help with this question. Why does every woman in the world, it seems, feel entitled to ask new moms if they are breastfeeding their babies? How should new moms respond politely to this question? If you say yes, you may or may not be lying. If you say no, you will be judged. If you give an evasive answer, people will assume you are not and you will be judged as well.22 Surely, Rose has a special prerogative (co-parent excluded) to determine whether, when, how, and to whom to reveal how she feeds her baby. To make the case interesting for our purposes, let us stipulate that Rose is bottle-feeding, not breastfeeding. Just as Mickey induced a loud silence context for Shavar and Jacqueline for Camila, Rose is complaining that other women (let's call them “Nosy Noras”) are inducing a loud silence context for her. If you will forgive me for not answering that question, I'll forgive you for asking. If that were any of your business, you would know already! Thank you; the baby is being well fed. It is kind of you to worry about him.23 Both Miss Manners and Abby seem to believe that when Nosy Nora asks Rose, “How do you feed your baby?” Nora hasn't induced a loud silence context at all. If Rose opts out the correct way, Rose can opt out silently. To opt out the correct way, of course, Rose must do more than mouth the correct words in the correct order. To pull off any of these retorts, Rose must say them with the appropriate conviction, panache, and grace. She must transform the guilty and abashed, “I'd rather not to say,” which reveals too much, into the principled and affronted, “I will not say,” which, in the best case, reveals nothing. Earlier, we stipulated that Jacqueline and Camila's case was not like this. But exactly in what sense “couldn't” Camila silently opt out? If Camila had said, with the appropriate conviction, panache, and grace and with the right suggestion of affronted dignity, “If you forgive me for not answering that question, I'll forgive you for asking,” would Jacqueline have learned that Camila has cancer? I don't think so. The sense in which Camila couldn't silently opt out is exactly the same sense in which Rose, prior to reading the Dear Abby and Miss Manners columns, couldn't silently opt out. What they both lacked was not the option to reveal nothing but the ability to cognize and execute that option. They lacked a capacity, ability, or skill. If Rose and Camila thought for long and hard enough about how to answer their interlocutors' questions, they could, in principle, arrive at Dear Abby's and Miss Manners' advice. There is nothing exotic about this. We have all thought up ingenious, sizzling comebacks only hours after our need for them has passed. Maybe we were mulling over the conversation in our head or describing it to friends. Or maybe the right answer just spontaneously “bubbled up” from our subpersonal consciousness, in the way that the correct answer to exam questions used to spontaneously “bubble up” to me hours after I had submitted the test. In all of these cases, what we lack is not the knowledge, per se, but access to the relevant knowledge. We can't retrieve and so can't make use of what we know in the right time frame. It's worth emphasizing exactly how fast conversation moves and how communicatively perilous delays are. As some of us have found out the hard way, even memorizing a witty comeback ex ante is no guarantee that you can access the knowledge with the right speed in the right context. From empirical linguistic anthropology, we now know that in face-to-face conversation, an addressee has exactly 1 s, from the end of her interlocutor's turn, in which to begin speaking.24 Anything longer is perceived as awkward, conversationally incompetent, or deeply communicatively significant. You ask me a question in Q&A, and I look at you for 3 s before saying anything at all. What has happened? We want to say: I was either dumbstruck by your question, and so you got one over on me, or I was shocked by the badness of your question, in which case my pause is getting one over on you. Either way, this isn't something I normally want to happen. But even this undersells conversation's speed.25 For within the 1 s window, delays of only 300 ms already carry information about the addressee's mental state. At only 600 ms, you will perceive my delay as intentional. We know that interlocutors reliably decode and have introspective access to the information that these fraction-of-a-fraction of a second delays carry (although they may not know how they know it). A co","PeriodicalId":47999,"journal":{"name":"Philosophy & Public Affairs","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":3.3000,"publicationDate":"2023-09-25","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":"0","resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"Philosophy & Public Affairs","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.1111/papa.12249","RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"Q1","JCRName":"ETHICS","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0

Abstract

Individuals…exude expressions.1 Performers can stop giving expressions but cannot stop giving them off.2 Defense attorney Mickey Haller (and protagonist of the fictional series Lincoln Lawyer) has his witness exactly where he wants him.3 Anton Shavar isn't on trial. But Haller wants to insinuate that Shavar committed the murders that Haller's client stands accused of committing. First, he needs to insinuate that Shavar knows how to orchestrate a hit. Haller asks about Shavar's former job: “I have a background in formal intelligence in Israel.” So he was in the Mossad? Shavar replies: “I did not say that.” Haller repeats the question: “Were you in the Mossad? An organization which is known to carry out targeted assassinations?” The prosecution objects. Then a man at the back of the court room stands up. He announces that he is Mr. Shavar's counsel and that “Mr. Shavar's past employment in Israel, whatever it may be, has no bearing on this case. It could jeopardize the national security of one of this country's closest allies.” Haller smirks. Bingo. “It's all right, Your Honor, I'll take that as a yes.” Just by asking, “Were you in the Mossad?” Haller had trapped Shavar. All of his available options became bad. Shavar could tell the truth, but the cost would be too high. Shavar knew that Haller would use this information to smear his good name. Shavar could lie, but the risk would be too high: under oath, to lie is to commit a felony offense. Or he could stay silent. But that too was a bad choice. That Shavar stayed silent revealed that Shavar had good reason to stay silent. And, as Haller's quip “I'll take that as a yes” dramatized, Shavar thereby revealed that he worked for Mossad.4 Courtrooms have elaborate rules to attempt to defuse what I call the problem of loud silence. In Lincoln Lawyer, the judge instructs the jury to disregard Haller's final quip. If the jury does what it should, it will deliberate without taking into account the information that Haller extracted through Shavar's silence. But without formal rules of evidence and deliberation, everyday interactions offer no such kindness. The right sort of question put to us, in the right sort of way, can leave us with only three bad options: to lie; to speak truthfully and reveal what we do not want to reveal; and to stay silent and reveal what we do not want to reveal anyway. I call this the problem of loud silence. The right sort of question, put the right sort of way, can do worse still. A tell-tale pause, a barely perceptible facial expression, a subtle vocal change, an odd word choice: all have the potential to reveal sensitive information. You might ask me a prying question, not because you want to know what I will say but because you want to see how I will react. Face-to-face conversation, then, renders us uniquely informationally vulnerable to each other. We are porous beings, our information often escapes from us against our will, and we can exploit this vulnerability in order to extract information from each other. Against a sufficiently powerful mind control machine, I am defenseless, and there is nothing I can do to improve my defenses. But against prying questions, I can martial some protection, and I can improve that protection over time. As any good poker player knows, the more I learn to bring my “tells” under voluntary control, that is, the more that I learn to manage the information that I both voluntarily and non-voluntarily exude, the less vulnerable I become to your questions. Drawing from the work of mid-century sociologist Goffman,5 I call this latter capacity poise. In the arms race between those who would pry and those who would have poise, what safeguards does morality offer? In particular, when is a prying question not just boorish, uncouth, or obnoxious but genuinely wrongful? And even more particularly, when does a prying question not just wrong but wrong because it violates the addressee's privacy rights? In other words, when does an intrusive question not just offend but intrude? I propose two different principles. (I remain neutral on which one is correct.) The first principle: if p is my private information, then I have a right against you asking me p? iff, in asking me p?, you thereby undermine my effective control over whether, when, and how to reveal p to you. The second principle: if p is my private information, then I have a right against you asking me p? iff you could reasonably expect that in asking me p?, you would thereby undermine my effective control over whether, when, and how to reveal p to you. (This is an approximation, actually. There are some book-keeping issues I consider later.) These principles say that you may not ask me questions about private matters that also force private information out of me. I can force information from you even if I do not coerce you to answer my question. Compare two ways that I can force you to remain seated. I can say, “Sit there, or I'll shoot.” That's coercion. Or I can press my hand onto your shoulder, so that you cannot physically rise. Interestingly, we do not have a general right against prying questions. If you ask me a question about where I would like to eat and you thereby force information out of me, you have not violated any of my rights. I will assume, at the outset, that our intuitions are right. Bad questions do violate our privacy rights. The question is: how could this be possible? Some “conversational libertarians” will not like this starting point.6 Conversational libertarians think that bad questions can be tacky or boorish. But they do not think that bad questions can be wrongful, or at least, not wrongful because they are rights violating. I ask for such readers' patience. My analysis of why bad questions violate our privacy rights also constitutes an argument that they do. I also assume, at the outset, that we do have a class of rights that deserve the name privacy rights. These privacy rights function to protect “my” information. My medical diagnoses, sexual history, and religious background, but not the identity of the university at which I work, are “my” information in this special sense. We have a special and legitimate interest in maintaining a kind of discretionary control over to whom, when, whether, and how to reveal “our” information. This interest, in turn, grounds and justifies our privacy rights.7 And this interest may be grounded in or explained or justified by a more basic interest or capacity still. This vision has its skeptics. Famously, Thomson points out that many of the paradigmatic “privacy violations” are also other sorts of rights violations.8 If I break into your laptop to read your love letters to Justin Bieber, I may have violated your privacy rights, but I have definitely violated your property rights. If a man on the subway pulls my skirt down, he may have violated my privacy rights, but he's definitely violated my right against bodily trespass. If that's correct, then what work is there left for privacy rights to do? Unlike the privacy violations that typically exercise moral philosophers, bad questions do not seem to violate any rights beyond my privacy rights. For the privacy skeptic, then, one take-away from my paper is that privacy rights have some real work to do after all. I have arranged this paper in the following way. In the next section, I will raise a skeptical challenge for myself and for White's recent discussion of prying questions.9 Though prying questions might express disrespect or entitlement (the challenge goes), surely they are not rights violations. A question like, “Do you have cancer?” is better analogized to a clueless or entitled request for a favor, not to peeping through a curtain. In order to respond to the worry, in Section III, I introduce three key concepts, each inspired by the work of Goffman: informational self-control; poise; and mentalism. In the fourth section, I use these concepts to defend what I call the Bad Question Principle. I suggest that the Bad Question Principle flows from the same interests that ground our privacy rights and show why the preceding discussion should convince even the privacy skeptic that we have privacy rights. Then I distinguish two different interpretations of the BQP and draw out the consequences of each interpretation. In the final section, I tease out some further questions that my analysis raises. I ask how far our rights against prying-like behavior extend. I argue it is sometimes permissible to ask via email what we cannot ask face-to-face. I show that my discussion may reveal an unexpected function of certain politeness norms, which may in turn ground (some of) their value. And I close by considering the value of our porousness, specifically in response to questions. Our imperfect control over our poise is central, I suggest, not just for our capacity to project authenticity but also to our capacity to engage in certain kinds of politeness strategies. Camila is suffering from early stage cancer. She is a private person, however, and she isn't ready to tell her coworkers. She especially isn't ready to tell Jacqueline, the departmental busybody. Unfortunately, Jacqueline has noticed that Camila has been looking sicker and sicker; that she has been taking time off work; and that she often cries in the bathroom. And, like many busybodies, Jacqueline just has a knack for knowing what's wrong with others. Jacqueline stops by Camila's office and asks, out of the blue, “Do you have cancer?” Compare this all to the way we might describe merely boorish, obnoxious, and out-of-touch requests. Suppose that my undergraduate student, Tommy, asks me, for no particularly good reason, “Can you read and return this draft to me in an hour?”11 The request would irritate me. It may even anger me. I'd ask myself, “Who does Tommy think he is?” I'd wonder why Tommy feels so entitled to my time or where he found the chutzpah to ask this. For all that, I would not accuse Tommy of prying, probing, putting me under a microscope, or otherwise violating my rights. His request might have expressed something morally objectionable, but it did not expose me. Say that a question is expressively problematic iff, in asking it, the speaker expresses something morally objectionable. Tommy's request is expressively problematic because it expresses a kind of entitlement to my time. Say that a question pries or intrudes iff, in asking it, the speaker violates the addressee's privacy rights. Jacqueline's question may be expressively problematic, and expressively problematic questions may or may not wrong, some or all of the time. But if expressively problematic questions (per se) wrong at all, they wrong in virtue of what they communicate.12 Here I am not interested in what Jacqueline's question communicates or whether requests can wrong because of what they communicate. I am interested in why (it seems that) Jacqueline's question wrongs because it intrudes.13 Consider this analogy. You ask me, out of the blue, “Hey, can I borrow your blender?” Let's stipulate that this is genuinely a request, not a threat in disguise. The question, “Hey, can I borrow your blender?” is really the question, “Will you waive your property rights with respect to me and your blender?” Similarly, (you might reasonably think) the question, “Do you have cancer?” is really the question, “Will you waive your privacy rights with respect to me and the matter of whether you have cancer?” A request to waive a right R might be expressively problematic. It might even be wrongfully expressively problematic. But an expressively problematic request to waive a right R doesn't constitute a violation of R itself.14 Here's one disanalogy between the question, “Hey, can I borrow your blender?” and Jacqueline's question, “Do you have a cancer?” which (following White) I've built into the case itself. If you ask me, “Will you waive your property rights with respect to me and your blender?” I can tell you, “No,” and that will be the end of it. If Jacqueline were to ask Camila, “Will you waive your privacy rights with respect to me and the matter of whether you have cancer?” and Camila says, “No,” then Jacqueline may in fact get what she wants. For sometimes, to decline to waive one's privacy rights—whether by saying, “It's none of your business,” or “I won't answer,” or pointedly changing the subject—just is to give away one's private information. Following White, let's build some stipulations into the case.15 Camila finds herself with three options. She can tell Jacqueline the truth and so reveal what she does not want to reveal. She can stay silent and again reveal what she does not want to reveal. Or she can lie. Camila is staring down the same gun as Shavar. In other words, Jacqueline has created a loud silence problem for Camila. The question I will now investigate is this: just in virtue of creating a loud silence problem for Camila, has Jacqueline violated Camila's privacy rights? In other words: can we use the nature of loud silence problems to vindicate our intuition that Jacqueline has violated Camila's privacy rights? I will temporarily answer, “Yes,” and do my best to develop this line of response. I will ultimately reject it as misguided, but the errors will prove instructive for what's to come. Before doing this, let me add a few clarificatory remarks. Until now, I've described speakers as “staying silent” in response to a question. When describing courtrooms, that makes sense. On the stand, we can plead the fifth. Our attorney can object. In real speech situations, we rarely “stay silent” by literally staying silent. To use a term from H.P. Grice, say that a speaker who is “staying silent” in my sense opts out.16 We can opt out of conversations altogether or opt out of a conversation's subcomponents. I might say, “Sorry, kid, I'm busy,” to make clear that I'm not interested in conversing with you at all. When I opt out of a question you have posed to me, I make clear that I'm not interested in providing you an answer or, if I do not know the answer, telling you that I do not know the answer. (But note that a curt “Sorry, don't know”—delivered to the suspicious person who has just approached you, before she has said much of anything—can constitute an opt-out move.) Opt outs can range from the straightforward, “I'd rather not answer that,” to the facetious, “What lovely weather we're having,” to the disapproving, “I didn't hear you say that.” Once I responded to an obnoxious, out-of-the-blue question, “Are you carrying student loan debt? How much?” with a terse, “How much do you weigh?” Say that when a speaker faces a loud silence problem, she is in a context in which her decision to opt out of the question p? or the conversation altogether would significantly and justifiably raise or lower her interlocutor's credence that p.17 “Significantly” is a weasel word. I use it to emphasize that our silence can be problematically “loud” even when it licenses only very secure suspicions. But for the sake of simplicity, I will just focus on cases in which opting out generates knowledge. Say also that a speaker who asks p? induces a loud silence context when her act makes it the case that her interlocutor faces a loud silence problem. We can induce loud silence contexts intentionally and unintentionally. The claim under consideration is not the claim that whenever I ask someone p? and so induce a loud silence context for her, I thereby wrong her. If this were the claim, then we could—quite easily, without reaching for recherché scenarios—generate an overwhelming number of apparent counter-examples. I might ask my co-teacher, “Do you really like the Twilight movies?” and create a loud silence context of him. In fact, I did this recently, as banter, and I do not think that either of us think that I wronged him. Danny is my undergraduate student, and he's working with me on his senior thesis. I suspect that things aren't going well for Danny, and he's embarrassed about it. I also know that when things aren't going well for Danny, he never wants to tell me about it. When Danny walks into my office, I ask him, “How is the senior thesis going?” When we intentionally create loud silence contexts, (you might think), we undermine our interlocutors' capacity to choose whether or not to reveal some information to us. Since I do not have a right that you refrain from putting me in loud silence contexts, I do not have a right that you refrain from undermining my capacity to choose whether or not to reveal information to you. If this sounds like an uncomfortable conclusion, I think it is only because it is easy to confuse this claim with a related one. I have a right that you refrain from undermining my capacity to choose whether to tell you some information. You may not coerce me into telling you something, because, as a general matter, you may not coerce me to do anything. The difference is that tellings are always actions that I intentionally perform, whereas revealings needn't be. When I opt out in a loud silence context, I reveal something to you only in the sense that my action provides you with certain kinds of evidence. The claim under consideration is more restricted: whenever I ask someone p? and so induce a loud silence context for her with respect to her private information, I thereby wrong her. This proposal meshes with the intuitive thought that morality provides us special safeguards over “sensitive” information. In what sense does the bad questioner undermine her victim's control over her private information? Here's a first pass thought. Before Jacqueline said anything, Camila could permissibly choose to reveal her diagnosis to Jacqueline, and she could permissibly choose to keep it to herself. After Jacqueline asks her question, Camila cannot permissibly keep the information to herself, because she cannot permissibly lie to Jacqueline. (Bear with me on this assumption.) Camila has lost normative control over whether or not to reveal her diagnosis. And Camila lost this control because Jacqueline deliberately conspired to constrain Camila's permissible option set in just this way. Here's an analogy. Suppose Camila lives in an isolated house on a mountain road. Jacqueline is desperate to see the inside of Camila's living room. But Camila, who is shy and not a fan of Jacqueline, refuses to invite Jacqueline into her home. So Jacqueline concocts an elaborate and desperate plan. During a snowstorm, Jacqueline goes hiking in the woods near Camila's house. Jacqueline wears inadequate winter gear and doesn't bring a phone. Jacqueline intentionally brings herself near hypothermic death. She then walks to Camila's house, rings the doorbell, and begs for Camila to let her into her house. It seems to me that Camila is obligated to permit Jacqueline to enter her house. (And if Camila doesn't voluntarily invite Jacqueline in, it seems that Jacqueline can permissibly force her way indoors to save her life.) In carrying out this manipulative scheme, Jacqueline deliberately conspires to undermine Camila's normative control over her property. In entering Camila's house, Jacqueline does not violate Camila's privacy rights, at least not in the traditional sense. (Even if she forces her way inside, Jacqueline at best infringes them.) But Jacqueline's manipulative scheme clearly fails to respect Camila's underlying and legitimate interest in maintaining certain kinds of control over who enters her home and when. Similarly, Jacqueline's bad question might not violate Camila's privacy rights in the traditional sense. But her bad question is its own kind of manipulative scheme, which likewise fails to respect the interests that ultimately ground Camila's privacy rights. Unfortunately, this kind of account stumbles early on. For Camila loses normative control in the relevant respect only if Camila cannot permissibly lie to Jacqueline about her diagnosis. This assumption is, at best, dubious. First, it just seems plainly clear that in response to and because of Jacqueline's inappropriate question, Camila can lie to Jacqueline. If Camila did lie to Jacqueline, Jacqueline would not have a legitimate complaint against Camila. Jacqueline would have no one to blame but herself. And if you were Camila's friend, and if Camila were fretting to you about whether to lie or not in such a situation, you'd almost certainly counsel her, “Jacqueline, in putting that question to you, gave up her right to a good faith reply.” Even a stringent moralist like Kant, in his Lectures on Evil, acknowledges that “if I cannot save myself by maintaining my silence, then my lie is a weapon of defence.”19 For otherwise, “we might often become victims of the wickedness of others who were ready to abuse our truthfulness.”20 White likewise observes, “If dodging the question or refusing to answer would allow [Jacqueline] to deduce her secret, she may lie…That the lie is permissible and the question impermissible is clearly no coincidence.”21 There is more to say in favor of this viewpoint. In the hypothermia scheme, Jacqueline manipulates the situation in order to dramatically change her underlying interest in accessing Camila's house: her life depends upon it. If Jacqueline doesn't gain access to her house, she will die. In the bad question scheme, Jaqueline's question doesn't change the nature or urgency of her interest in learning Camila's diagnosis. If Camila were to respond with the lie, “I don't have cancer,” her lie would not set Jacqueline's interests back any more than would her out-of-the-blue assertion, “I don't have cancer.” This is not to say that these lies don't set Jacqueline's interests back. Jacqueline, like all agents, has an interest in gaining knowledge and avoiding false beliefs, and lies undermine that interest. But given Jacqueline intentionally conspired to bring her interest in avoiding false beliefs into conflict with Camila's interest in protecting her privacy and given that her underlying interests have otherwise not changed, it would seem perverse for morality to decide in Jacqueline's favor. Here's a last-ditch effort to save the normative control explanation. Let us concede that it is permissible for Camila to lie to Jacqueline, and it is permissible in part or in whole because Jacqueline intentionally asked Camila a question that created a loud silence context about her private information. Still, you might think, Jacqueline conspired to create a situation in which Camila infringed Jacqueline's rights—justifiably so, of course, but an infringement, nonetheless. And as infringements sometimes do, that might leave a residue. Camila might owe Jacqueline some kind of “compensation”—perhaps an apology, if Jacqueline ever learns the truth, for example, or more metaphorical compensation, in the form of a pang of conscience or regret. Still, even if we concede this point, could this plausibly explain the facts that we aim to vindicate? In creating a situation in which Camila has no reasonable choice but to infringe Jacqueline's right against deception, has Jacqueline thereby violated Camila's privacy? To compel me to infringe your right R in order to protect my right R* does not seem to thereby violate my right R* or even to disrespect the interests that ground my right R*. It is rather to disrespect my interest in not infringing your rights. We have been investigating a certain analysis of prying question, one on which Jacqueline intrudes insofar as she intentionally undermines Camila's normative control over the disclosure of her private information. That analysis has floundered on a difficult-to-defend presupposition. If this isn't the correct story about why Jacqueline's question intrudes, what is? The problem, I will argue, is that we have misunderstood the sense in which Camila can't conceal her information from Jacqueline. It's not that Camila cannot permissibly conceal her information from Jacqueline. Rather, Camila cannot conceal her information from Jacqueline in a more flat-footed sense. She is not able to do so. She lacks the skill it would require. Jacqueline has undermined Camila's effective control over her private information and, in doing so, has wronged her. Or so I will argue in Section IV. In this section, I will set the stage for that argument. Here I introduce a more realistic vision of conversation. Face-to-face conversations occur rapidly, between flesh-and-blood people staring into each other's eyes, with only imperfect access to their knowledge and imperfect self-control, and with an extraordinary capacity for mind-reading. Given this, conversation renders us uniquely vulnerable to each other. Ask me just the right questions, in just the right way, and you can turn me into an open book—without inducing a loud silence context at all. To describe these vulnerabilities with greater precision, I will also introduce a suite of new terminology, grounded in the work of Goffman. But first, I want to introduce a real-life Camila, an anonymous woman who wrote into an advice column a few years ago. To make it easy to refer to her, I'm going to call her Rose. By studying the advice columnist's reply and Rose's overall predicament, I will argue that loud silence contexts are much more fraught and interesting than the previous discussion suggests. On behalf of all new moms, please help with this question. Why does every woman in the world, it seems, feel entitled to ask new moms if they are breastfeeding their babies? How should new moms respond politely to this question? If you say yes, you may or may not be lying. If you say no, you will be judged. If you give an evasive answer, people will assume you are not and you will be judged as well.22 Surely, Rose has a special prerogative (co-parent excluded) to determine whether, when, how, and to whom to reveal how she feeds her baby. To make the case interesting for our purposes, let us stipulate that Rose is bottle-feeding, not breastfeeding. Just as Mickey induced a loud silence context for Shavar and Jacqueline for Camila, Rose is complaining that other women (let's call them “Nosy Noras”) are inducing a loud silence context for her. If you will forgive me for not answering that question, I'll forgive you for asking. If that were any of your business, you would know already! Thank you; the baby is being well fed. It is kind of you to worry about him.23 Both Miss Manners and Abby seem to believe that when Nosy Nora asks Rose, “How do you feed your baby?” Nora hasn't induced a loud silence context at all. If Rose opts out the correct way, Rose can opt out silently. To opt out the correct way, of course, Rose must do more than mouth the correct words in the correct order. To pull off any of these retorts, Rose must say them with the appropriate conviction, panache, and grace. She must transform the guilty and abashed, “I'd rather not to say,” which reveals too much, into the principled and affronted, “I will not say,” which, in the best case, reveals nothing. Earlier, we stipulated that Jacqueline and Camila's case was not like this. But exactly in what sense “couldn't” Camila silently opt out? If Camila had said, with the appropriate conviction, panache, and grace and with the right suggestion of affronted dignity, “If you forgive me for not answering that question, I'll forgive you for asking,” would Jacqueline have learned that Camila has cancer? I don't think so. The sense in which Camila couldn't silently opt out is exactly the same sense in which Rose, prior to reading the Dear Abby and Miss Manners columns, couldn't silently opt out. What they both lacked was not the option to reveal nothing but the ability to cognize and execute that option. They lacked a capacity, ability, or skill. If Rose and Camila thought for long and hard enough about how to answer their interlocutors' questions, they could, in principle, arrive at Dear Abby's and Miss Manners' advice. There is nothing exotic about this. We have all thought up ingenious, sizzling comebacks only hours after our need for them has passed. Maybe we were mulling over the conversation in our head or describing it to friends. Or maybe the right answer just spontaneously “bubbled up” from our subpersonal consciousness, in the way that the correct answer to exam questions used to spontaneously “bubble up” to me hours after I had submitted the test. In all of these cases, what we lack is not the knowledge, per se, but access to the relevant knowledge. We can't retrieve and so can't make use of what we know in the right time frame. It's worth emphasizing exactly how fast conversation moves and how communicatively perilous delays are. As some of us have found out the hard way, even memorizing a witty comeback ex ante is no guarantee that you can access the knowledge with the right speed in the right context. From empirical linguistic anthropology, we now know that in face-to-face conversation, an addressee has exactly 1 s, from the end of her interlocutor's turn, in which to begin speaking.24 Anything longer is perceived as awkward, conversationally incompetent, or deeply communicatively significant. You ask me a question in Q&A, and I look at you for 3 s before saying anything at all. What has happened? We want to say: I was either dumbstruck by your question, and so you got one over on me, or I was shocked by the badness of your question, in which case my pause is getting one over on you. Either way, this isn't something I normally want to happen. But even this undersells conversation's speed.25 For within the 1 s window, delays of only 300 ms already carry information about the addressee's mental state. At only 600 ms, you will perceive my delay as intentional. We know that interlocutors reliably decode and have introspective access to the information that these fraction-of-a-fraction of a second delays carry (although they may not know how they know it). A co
不好的问题!
个人…散发出expressions.1表演者可以停止表达,但不能停止释放辩护律师米奇·哈勒(虚构剧集《林肯律师》的主角)让他的证人在他想要的地方安东·沙瓦尔不是在受审但哈勒想暗示沙瓦尔犯下了哈勒的客户被指控犯下的谋杀罪。首先,他需要暗示沙瓦尔知道如何策划暗杀。哈勒问起沙瓦尔以前的工作:“我在以色列有正式情报背景。”所以他是摩萨德的?沙瓦尔回答说:“我可没这么说。”哈勒重复了这个问题:“你在摩萨德吗?”一个以定点暗杀著称的组织?”控方反对。然后,法庭后面的一个男人站了起来。他宣称自己是沙瓦尔先生的律师,“沙瓦尔先生过去在以色列的工作经历,无论如何,都与本案无关。”这可能会危及美国最亲密盟友之一的国家安全。”哈勒笑了起来。宾果。“没关系,法官大人,我就当你同意了。”只要问"你在摩萨德工作过吗"哈勒把沙瓦尔困住了。他所有的选择都变坏了。沙瓦可以说出真相,但代价太高了。沙瓦知道哈勒会利用这些信息来抹黑他的好名声。沙瓦尔可以撒谎,但风险太大了:在宣誓后,撒谎是重罪。或者他可以保持沉默。但这也是一个糟糕的选择。沙瓦尔保持沉默表明,沙瓦尔有充分的理由保持沉默。而且,正如哈勒的妙语“我就当那是肯定的”所戏剧化的那样,沙瓦尔由此暴露了他为摩萨德工作的事实。法庭有精心制定的规则,试图化解我所说的大声沉默的问题。在《林肯律师》中,法官指示陪审团不要理会哈勒最后的俏皮话。如果陪审团做了它应该做的事,它会在不考虑哈勒从沙瓦尔的沉默中获取的信息的情况下进行审议。但如果没有正式的证据和审议规则,日常互动就不会带来这种善意。以正确的方式向我们提出正确的问题,只会给我们留下三个糟糕的选择:撒谎;说真话,说出我们不想说的话;保持沉默,揭露我们本来就不想揭露的事。我把这个问题称为“大声沉默”。正确的问题,用正确的方式提问,可能会造成更糟的结果。一个告密的停顿,一个难以察觉的面部表情,一个微妙的声音变化,一个奇怪的用词:所有这些都有可能泄露敏感信息。你可能会问我一个刺探性的问题,不是因为你想知道我会说什么,而是因为你想看看我会作何反应。因此,面对面的交谈使我们在信息上非常容易受到对方的伤害。我们是漏洞百出的生物,我们的信息经常违背我们的意愿从我们身上逃脱,我们可以利用这个弱点来从彼此身上获取信息。面对一个足够强大的精神控制机器,我毫无防御能力,而且我无法做任何事情来提高我的防御能力。但对于窥探性的问题,我可以采取一些保护措施,并且随着时间的推移,我可以改进这种保护措施。任何优秀的扑克玩家都知道,我越是学会主动控制自己的“信息”,也就是说,我越是学会管理自己自愿和非自愿泄露的信息,我就越不容易受到你问题的影响。根据上世纪中叶社会学家戈夫曼(Goffman)的研究,我把后一种能力称为“平衡”(poise)。在爱打探者和沉稳者之间的军备竞赛中,道德能提供什么保障?特别是,什么时候一个窥探的问题不仅是粗鲁、粗鲁或令人讨厌的,而且是真正的错误?更具体地说,什么时候一个窥探问题不仅是错误的,而且是错误的,因为它侵犯了收件人的隐私权?换句话说,什么时候一个侵入性的问题不仅仅是冒犯而是侵入?我提出两个不同的原则。(我对哪一种说法是正确的保持中立。)第一个原则:如果p是我的私人信息,那么我有权反对你问我p?我,你在问我吗?,你因此削弱了我对是否、何时以及如何向你透露p的有效控制。第二条原则:如果p是我的私人信息,那么我有权反对你问我p?如果你能合理地期望在问我p?,你就会因此削弱我对是否、何时以及如何向你透露p的有效控制。(实际上,这是一个近似值。有些簿记问题我稍后再考虑。)这些原则说,你不能问我私人问题,也不能强迫我说出私人信息。即使我不强迫你回答我的问题,我也可以强迫你提供信息。比较一下我强迫你坐着的两种方法。我可以说"坐那儿,不然我开枪了"这是强迫。 或者我可以把手按在你的肩膀上,这样你就站不起来了。有趣的是,我们并没有反对窥探问题的一般权利。如果你问我想去哪里吃饭,并以此逼问我,你并没有侵犯我的任何权利。首先,我假定我们的直觉是正确的。糟糕的问题确实侵犯了我们的隐私权。问题是:这怎么可能?一些“健谈的自由意志主义者”不会喜欢这样的起点会话自由主义者认为糟糕的问题可能是俗气或粗鲁的。但他们不认为糟糕的问题可能是错误的,或者至少,因为它们侵犯了权利而不是错误的。我希望读者们能有耐心。我对为什么糟糕的问题侵犯了我们的隐私权的分析也构成了一个论点,即它们确实侵犯了我们的隐私权。我也假设,在一开始,我们确实有一类权利可以称为隐私权。这些隐私权的作用是保护“我的”信息。我的医疗诊断、性史和宗教背景,但不是我工作的大学的身份,都是这种特殊意义上的“我的”信息。对于向谁、何时、是否以及如何披露“我们的”信息,保持一种自由裁量的控制,对我们有特殊的、合法的利益。这种兴趣反过来又为我们的隐私权提供了依据和理由这种兴趣可能是建立在一个更基本的兴趣或能力的基础上,或被解释或证明是合理的。有人对这一愿景持怀疑态度。汤姆森著名地指出,许多典型的“侵犯隐私”同时也是其他形式的权利侵犯如果我侵入你的笔记本电脑,看你写给贾斯汀·比伯的情书,我可能侵犯了你的隐私权,但我绝对侵犯了你的财产权。如果一个男人在地铁上拉下我的裙子,他可能侵犯了我的隐私权,但他绝对侵犯了我不受身体侵犯的权利。如果这是正确的,那么隐私权还有什么工作要做呢?不像道德哲学家通常会侵犯隐私,糟糕的问题似乎不会侵犯我的隐私权之外的任何权利。那么,对于隐私怀疑论者来说,我的论文得出的一个结论是,隐私权毕竟有一些真正的工作要做。我将这篇论文按如下方式整理。在下一节中,我将对自己和怀特最近关于窥探问题的讨论提出质疑尽管打探问题可能会表现出不尊重或权利(挑战是这样的),但它们肯定不是侵犯人权。比如,“你得了癌症吗?”这句话最好被比喻成毫无头绪或有理由的请求帮助,而不是透过帘子偷窥。为了回应这种担忧,在第三节中,我介绍了三个关键概念,每个概念都受到戈夫曼工作的启发:信息自我控制;风度;和唯心主义。在第四部分,我用这些概念来捍卫我所谓的坏问题原则。我认为,“坏问题原则”源于我们隐私权的基础利益,并表明为什么前面的讨论甚至应该说服隐私怀疑论者我们拥有隐私权。然后,我区分了对BQP的两种不同解释,并得出了每种解释的后果。在最后一节,我梳理了我的分析提出的一些进一步的问题。我问的是,我们对类似窥探行为的权利有多大。我认为,有时通过电子邮件询问我们不能面对面询问的问题是允许的。我表明,我的讨论可能揭示了某些礼貌规范的一种意想不到的功能,这可能反过来奠定了它们的(部分)价值。最后,我想谈谈我们的多孔性的价值,特别是在回答问题时。我认为,我们对姿态的不完美控制是关键,这不仅关系到我们表现真实性的能力,也关系到我们采取某种礼貌策略的能力。卡米拉患有早期癌症。然而,她是一个注重隐私的人,她还没有准备好告诉她的同事。她还没准备好告诉杰奎琳,那个部门里爱管闲事的人。不幸的是,杰奎琳注意到卡米拉的病情越来越严重;她一直在休假;她还经常在浴室里哭。和许多爱管闲事的人一样,杰奎琳有一种知道别人哪里出了问题的诀窍。杰奎琳在卡米拉的办公室停下来,突然问道:“你得了癌症吗?”将这一切与我们可能描述的仅仅是粗鲁、令人讨厌和脱离联系的请求的方式进行比较。假设我的本科生汤米无缘无故地问我:“你能在一小时内把这篇稿子读完并还给我吗?”这个要求会使我生气。这甚至会激怒我。我会问自己,汤米以为自己是谁我想知道为什么汤米觉得自己有资格占用我的时间或者他哪里来的厚颜无耻来问这个问题。 因为只有当卡米拉不能向杰奎琳谎称自己的诊断时,卡米拉才会在相关方面失去规范性控制。这种假设充其量是可疑的。首先,很明显,为了回应杰奎琳不恰当的问题,卡米拉可以对杰奎琳撒谎。如果卡米拉对杰奎琳撒谎,杰奎琳就没有理由控告卡米拉。杰奎琳只能怪她自己。如果你是卡米拉的朋友,如果卡米拉让你纠结在这种情况下该不该撒谎,你几乎肯定会劝她,“杰奎琳向你提出这个问题,等于放弃了她得到真诚回答的权利。”即使像康德这样严格的道德家,在他的《恶论》中也承认,“如果我不能通过保持沉默来拯救自己,那么我的谎言就是一种防御武器。”否则,“我们就可能常常成为别人邪恶的牺牲品,他们随时准备滥用我们的诚实。”怀特同样观察到,“如果回避问题或拒绝回答可以让[杰奎琳]推断出她的秘密,她可能会撒谎……谎言是允许的,问题是不允许的,这显然不是巧合。”支持这一观点的理由还有很多。在低温疗法方案中,杰奎琳操纵了局势,以戏剧性地改变她进入卡米拉家的潜在兴趣:她的生命取决于此。如果杰奎琳进不去她家,她会死的。在糟糕的问题方案中,杰奎琳的问题并没有改变她对了解卡米拉诊断的兴趣的性质和紧迫性。如果卡米拉以“我没有癌症”的谎言来回应,她的谎言不会比她突然的断言“我没有癌症”更让杰奎琳感兴趣。这并不是说这些谎言不会阻碍杰奎琳的利益。杰奎琳和所有特工一样,对获取知识和避免错误信念有兴趣,而谎言破坏了这种兴趣。但是考虑到杰奎琳故意让她避免错误信念的兴趣与卡米拉保护隐私的兴趣发生冲突,考虑到她的潜在利益没有改变,道德上对杰奎琳有利似乎是反常的。这里是保存规范控制解释的最后努力。让我们承认卡米拉对杰奎琳撒谎是允许的,部分或全部是允许的,因为杰奎琳故意问了卡米拉一个问题,创造了一个关于她私人信息的大声沉默的环境。不过,你可能会认为,杰奎琳合谋制造了一种局面,使卡米拉侵犯了杰奎琳的权利——当然,这是正当的,但无论如何,这是一种侵犯。就像侵权有时所做的那样,这可能会留下残留物。卡米拉可能欠杰奎琳某种“补偿”——也许是道歉,如果杰奎琳知道了真相,例如,或者更多隐喻性的补偿,以良心的痛苦或后悔的形式。然而,即使我们承认这一点,这能合理地解释我们想要证明的事实吗?在卡米拉没有合理的选择只能侵犯杰奎琳的反欺骗权的情况下,杰奎琳是否因此侵犯了卡米拉的隐私?为了保护我的R*权利而强迫我侵犯你的R*权利,似乎并不因此侵犯我的R*权利,甚至不尊重我的R*权利的基础利益。我不想侵犯你的权利,这是对我的不尊重。我们一直在调查一个关于窥探问题的分析,其中杰奎琳故意破坏卡米拉对她的私人信息披露的规范控制。这种分析在一个难以辩护的前提下陷入了困境。如果这不是关于杰奎琳的问题闯入的正确故事,那什么才是?我认为,问题在于,我们误解了卡米拉无法向杰奎琳隐瞒她的信息。并不是说卡米拉不能向杰奎琳隐瞒她的信息。更确切地说,卡米拉无法对杰奎琳隐瞒她的信息。她不能这样做。她缺乏所需的技能。杰奎琳破坏了卡米拉对她的私人信息的有效控制,这样做是冤屈了她。我将在第四节中进行论证,在这一节中,我将为这个论证奠定基础。在这里,我将介绍一种更现实的对话方式。面对面的对话发生得很快,有血有肉的人盯着对方的眼睛,只有不完美的知识和不完美的自我控制,以及非凡的读心术。鉴于此,谈话使我们在彼此面前变得特别脆弱。 只有600毫秒,你会认为我的延迟是故意的。我们知道对话者可以可靠地解码并内省地访问这些一秒延迟所携带的信息(尽管他们可能不知道他们是如何知道的)。一个公司
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
求助全文
约1分钟内获得全文 求助全文
来源期刊
CiteScore
3.90
自引率
4.50%
发文量
23
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
确定
请完成安全验证×
copy
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
右上角分享
点击右上角分享
0
联系我们:info@booksci.cn Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。 Copyright © 2023 布克学术 All rights reserved.
京ICP备2023020795号-1
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术官方微信