Guest Editor’s Introduction

IF 1.3 Q2 ETHNIC STUDIES
Siphiwe Ndlovu
{"title":"Guest Editor’s Introduction","authors":"Siphiwe Ndlovu","doi":"10.5325/critphilrace.11.2.0259","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"This Special Issue comes at a time when African countries and the Global South in general are facing unprecedented crises in securing energy to power their economies. The crises are necessitated largely by the developed Western countries exerting enormous power and pressure upon the developing world to move away from fossil fuels, while at the same time the West is increasing its uptake on fossils. However, with critical self-reflection we are able to understand that a crisis of this nature is not without historical precedence, as it is preceded by a series of other forms of injustices meted out upon the formerly and still colonized peoples. And not long ago, the COVID-19 pandemic on the health front, and the handling thereof, showed just how skewed and divided the world still is and laid bare race-laden inequalities both at local and global levels. So to be sure, the current crises are part of the history of struggle against race-based social injustices and demonstrate Western desire to continue its stranglehold over its former colonies. And although the energy transition is dubbed the “Just Energy Transition,” for those in the developing world who are negatively affected, there is clearly nothing “Just” about it. So whereas we generally tend to speak of social or historical injustices such as the energy crises and COVID-19, at an epistemological front we find cognitive injustice. Accordingly, the articles in this issue contribute to a series of responses by the anticolonial movement (broadly defined) in relation to injustice, particularly its epistemological ramifications on knowledge and knowledge production in the relation between the colonizer and the colonized, the center and the periphery. Furthermore, the historical exclusion of African and other non-European peoples from participation in reason had the effect that Africans in particular were precluded from philosophy itself, a phenomenon that African philosophy and associated disciplines are today still grappling with in the academy. So in a word, the articles make an important contribution insofar as reckoning with the impact that race and the history of racism has had in philosophy in particular, both as a discipline and as a human mental activity.It should be remembered that the exclusion of Africans from reason and eventually from philosophy is preceded by an earlier one, the exclusion of Africans from recognition at a human level, qua rational beings. One can talk of a history of depersonalizations and dehumanizations; of massacres and deracination inflicted upon the oppressed owing to the colonial encounter. This is why for a scholar and a philosopher of the periphery, to use Enrique Dussel’s term, philosophical inquiry cannot and ought not be divorced from human reality. In fact, scholars of the periphery often stress the need for philosophy not to abstract too much from reality; and for philosophy to confine itself with liberatory human ends, among other things. There are a number of thinkers of the periphery who famously harp upon this point. For instance, Lewis Gordon has introduced the concept of “disciplinary decadence” by which he laments the fetishization of methods and whereby disciplines become an end in themselves, thus not necessarily serving human needs. Other thinkers in this school of thought include the likes of Enrique Dussel, Charles Mills, Cornel West, Angela Davis, and George Yancy to mention but a few. Yancy speaks of the “Density project” with which he has a normative injunction upon Black philosophers. In a similar vein, Dussel remarks in the Philosophy of Liberation that “Philosophy, when it is really philosophy and not sophistry or ideology, does not ponder philosophy. It does not ponder philosophical texts, except as a pedagogical propaedeutic to provide itself with interpretive categories. Philosophy ponders the nonphilosophical; the reality.”1 This reality, as is averred, is in existential phenomenology, not merely objective reality or perhaps something out there existing on its own accord, but rather it is what Jean-Paul Sartre associates with “human reality,” which is reality as lived by people of flesh and blood. So in a world demarcated between center and periphery, human beings and subhumans, whites and Blacks, the anticolonial thinker cannot afford not to raise questions relating to social existence, “the reality.” Thus for those in the academy, one must be able to come to terms with the reality of non-Western and “non-scientific knowledges” (after Boaventura De Sousa Santos) not being recognized as credible knowledge, coupled with the possibility of being forgotten, of being completely wiped out from history. And, as we see with Bernard Matolino’s article in particular, this is the battle that African philosophy has vigorously had to deal with in the previous two or three decades.In the Western canon, philosophy is generally taken to begin with the Greeks and this, as is observed, is no historical accident but forms part of a project to relegate previous philosophical traditions to relative obscurity, and to preclude the rest of humanity from participation in reason. The idea is that for Western modernity to be a viable project, oppressed cultures must out of necessity be denied reason. On this very point, Frantz Fanon would remark in Black Skin White Masks in the following manner: “That victory [on the rational front] played cat and mouse; it made a fool of me. As the other put it, when I was present, it was not; when it was there, I was no longer.”2 In this regard Mogobe Ramose’s article notes how the Aristotlean concept of man as a rational animal becomes a misnomer insofar as this relates to the Black person. With this sleight of hand, previous civilizations such as the African (Egyptian) and Arab traditions in philosophy are supposed to vanish from history and from the epistemological landscape. In this regard, Mills’s insights will continue to haunt philosophy well into the future, long after his passing. Mills had noted that a typical philosophy program in the Westernized university will normally start off with the two Greek philosophers, namely Plato and Aristotle. From here it moves to cover the Middle Ages and probably end with theories on liberalism. And although this period covers a history of more than two thousand years of Western philosophy, there will be little or no mention of traditions that shaped philosophical thought prior to the Greeks.The above notwithstanding, the articles in this issue show, however, that not only are Africans and oppressed peoples endowed with reflective reason, but that they also possess a unique brand of philosophy. By and large, the articles not only affirm the epistemological standpoint of African philosophy but show its own genealogy, discourse, and objectives among other things.With these short remarks, the following articles cut across these thematic areas: metaphysics of race, epistemic racism, racial ontology, feminism, and decolonial literature. Accordingly, the article by Bernard Matolino begins by delving into the metaphysics of race and notes that while there is no proof that there are distinct races (after Kwame Appiah), race as a matter of social life is alive and relevant. Further, his article goes on to demonstrate how African philosophy emerged as a form of protest and native philosophers’ need to show that indigenous peoples always had a philosophy. In a similar vein, Edwin Etieyibo’s article discusses epistemic racism, and how color prejudice historically translated to other forms of racial injustices such as epistemic racism. His article makes use of the works of such thinkers as Anibal Quijano and Ramon Grosfoguel to trace the genealogy of such injustices in the modern period.Siphiwe Ndlovu’s article looks into the problem of Black marginality, particularly in the modern period. He locates his musings within the social contract tradition but suggests a reading of contemporary marginality through the lens of Mills’s racial contract. Accordingly, instead of seeing Black marginality as a function of exclusion or being cast outside the contract, the article argues that such marginality is due not from exclusions per se but rather from inclusion albeit only as junior—and therefore inferior—partners in the racial contract.Mogobe Ramose’s article begins by endorsing Kwasi Wiredu’s view that there is nothing wrong with African philosophy being preoccupied with questions that are not exactly identical to those of non-African philosophies. Furthermore, his article traces, through D. M. Goldenberg, the roots of anti-Black racism from “colour symbolism” among the Arabs in the classical world, through the Rabbinic era, and later taking the form of race prejudice in Christianity. At the crux of his article is the argument that the prevailing practice of fragmenting the human race into multiple bits and pieces is against the pursuit of justice and peace in human relations.The article by Zinhle ka’Nobuhlaluse considers Anika Mann’s arguments on race and feminist standpoint as an existential standpoint and foundation. She takes up Mamphela Ramphele’s initial autobiography, Mamphela Ramphele: A Life, to critically reflect on what the actions of “non-subservient Blackwomen” reveal about the lived experience of being Black and a woman under Apartheid South Africa.The article by Siseko Kumalo infuses decolonial and literary criticism as projects that may allow for a recognition of the “ontological legitimacy” of amaqaba (those who rejected colonial influences and education). Through a close reading of S. E. K. Mqhayi’s Intshayelelo: Imbali, the article engages with the question How does a model of inclusive national identity in South Africa, once established, get us to the point of recognition for the Indigene?","PeriodicalId":43337,"journal":{"name":"Critical Philosophy of Race","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":1.3000,"publicationDate":"2023-07-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":"0","resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"Critical Philosophy of Race","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.5325/critphilrace.11.2.0259","RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":null,"ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"Q2","JCRName":"ETHNIC STUDIES","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0

Abstract

This Special Issue comes at a time when African countries and the Global South in general are facing unprecedented crises in securing energy to power their economies. The crises are necessitated largely by the developed Western countries exerting enormous power and pressure upon the developing world to move away from fossil fuels, while at the same time the West is increasing its uptake on fossils. However, with critical self-reflection we are able to understand that a crisis of this nature is not without historical precedence, as it is preceded by a series of other forms of injustices meted out upon the formerly and still colonized peoples. And not long ago, the COVID-19 pandemic on the health front, and the handling thereof, showed just how skewed and divided the world still is and laid bare race-laden inequalities both at local and global levels. So to be sure, the current crises are part of the history of struggle against race-based social injustices and demonstrate Western desire to continue its stranglehold over its former colonies. And although the energy transition is dubbed the “Just Energy Transition,” for those in the developing world who are negatively affected, there is clearly nothing “Just” about it. So whereas we generally tend to speak of social or historical injustices such as the energy crises and COVID-19, at an epistemological front we find cognitive injustice. Accordingly, the articles in this issue contribute to a series of responses by the anticolonial movement (broadly defined) in relation to injustice, particularly its epistemological ramifications on knowledge and knowledge production in the relation between the colonizer and the colonized, the center and the periphery. Furthermore, the historical exclusion of African and other non-European peoples from participation in reason had the effect that Africans in particular were precluded from philosophy itself, a phenomenon that African philosophy and associated disciplines are today still grappling with in the academy. So in a word, the articles make an important contribution insofar as reckoning with the impact that race and the history of racism has had in philosophy in particular, both as a discipline and as a human mental activity.It should be remembered that the exclusion of Africans from reason and eventually from philosophy is preceded by an earlier one, the exclusion of Africans from recognition at a human level, qua rational beings. One can talk of a history of depersonalizations and dehumanizations; of massacres and deracination inflicted upon the oppressed owing to the colonial encounter. This is why for a scholar and a philosopher of the periphery, to use Enrique Dussel’s term, philosophical inquiry cannot and ought not be divorced from human reality. In fact, scholars of the periphery often stress the need for philosophy not to abstract too much from reality; and for philosophy to confine itself with liberatory human ends, among other things. There are a number of thinkers of the periphery who famously harp upon this point. For instance, Lewis Gordon has introduced the concept of “disciplinary decadence” by which he laments the fetishization of methods and whereby disciplines become an end in themselves, thus not necessarily serving human needs. Other thinkers in this school of thought include the likes of Enrique Dussel, Charles Mills, Cornel West, Angela Davis, and George Yancy to mention but a few. Yancy speaks of the “Density project” with which he has a normative injunction upon Black philosophers. In a similar vein, Dussel remarks in the Philosophy of Liberation that “Philosophy, when it is really philosophy and not sophistry or ideology, does not ponder philosophy. It does not ponder philosophical texts, except as a pedagogical propaedeutic to provide itself with interpretive categories. Philosophy ponders the nonphilosophical; the reality.”1 This reality, as is averred, is in existential phenomenology, not merely objective reality or perhaps something out there existing on its own accord, but rather it is what Jean-Paul Sartre associates with “human reality,” which is reality as lived by people of flesh and blood. So in a world demarcated between center and periphery, human beings and subhumans, whites and Blacks, the anticolonial thinker cannot afford not to raise questions relating to social existence, “the reality.” Thus for those in the academy, one must be able to come to terms with the reality of non-Western and “non-scientific knowledges” (after Boaventura De Sousa Santos) not being recognized as credible knowledge, coupled with the possibility of being forgotten, of being completely wiped out from history. And, as we see with Bernard Matolino’s article in particular, this is the battle that African philosophy has vigorously had to deal with in the previous two or three decades.In the Western canon, philosophy is generally taken to begin with the Greeks and this, as is observed, is no historical accident but forms part of a project to relegate previous philosophical traditions to relative obscurity, and to preclude the rest of humanity from participation in reason. The idea is that for Western modernity to be a viable project, oppressed cultures must out of necessity be denied reason. On this very point, Frantz Fanon would remark in Black Skin White Masks in the following manner: “That victory [on the rational front] played cat and mouse; it made a fool of me. As the other put it, when I was present, it was not; when it was there, I was no longer.”2 In this regard Mogobe Ramose’s article notes how the Aristotlean concept of man as a rational animal becomes a misnomer insofar as this relates to the Black person. With this sleight of hand, previous civilizations such as the African (Egyptian) and Arab traditions in philosophy are supposed to vanish from history and from the epistemological landscape. In this regard, Mills’s insights will continue to haunt philosophy well into the future, long after his passing. Mills had noted that a typical philosophy program in the Westernized university will normally start off with the two Greek philosophers, namely Plato and Aristotle. From here it moves to cover the Middle Ages and probably end with theories on liberalism. And although this period covers a history of more than two thousand years of Western philosophy, there will be little or no mention of traditions that shaped philosophical thought prior to the Greeks.The above notwithstanding, the articles in this issue show, however, that not only are Africans and oppressed peoples endowed with reflective reason, but that they also possess a unique brand of philosophy. By and large, the articles not only affirm the epistemological standpoint of African philosophy but show its own genealogy, discourse, and objectives among other things.With these short remarks, the following articles cut across these thematic areas: metaphysics of race, epistemic racism, racial ontology, feminism, and decolonial literature. Accordingly, the article by Bernard Matolino begins by delving into the metaphysics of race and notes that while there is no proof that there are distinct races (after Kwame Appiah), race as a matter of social life is alive and relevant. Further, his article goes on to demonstrate how African philosophy emerged as a form of protest and native philosophers’ need to show that indigenous peoples always had a philosophy. In a similar vein, Edwin Etieyibo’s article discusses epistemic racism, and how color prejudice historically translated to other forms of racial injustices such as epistemic racism. His article makes use of the works of such thinkers as Anibal Quijano and Ramon Grosfoguel to trace the genealogy of such injustices in the modern period.Siphiwe Ndlovu’s article looks into the problem of Black marginality, particularly in the modern period. He locates his musings within the social contract tradition but suggests a reading of contemporary marginality through the lens of Mills’s racial contract. Accordingly, instead of seeing Black marginality as a function of exclusion or being cast outside the contract, the article argues that such marginality is due not from exclusions per se but rather from inclusion albeit only as junior—and therefore inferior—partners in the racial contract.Mogobe Ramose’s article begins by endorsing Kwasi Wiredu’s view that there is nothing wrong with African philosophy being preoccupied with questions that are not exactly identical to those of non-African philosophies. Furthermore, his article traces, through D. M. Goldenberg, the roots of anti-Black racism from “colour symbolism” among the Arabs in the classical world, through the Rabbinic era, and later taking the form of race prejudice in Christianity. At the crux of his article is the argument that the prevailing practice of fragmenting the human race into multiple bits and pieces is against the pursuit of justice and peace in human relations.The article by Zinhle ka’Nobuhlaluse considers Anika Mann’s arguments on race and feminist standpoint as an existential standpoint and foundation. She takes up Mamphela Ramphele’s initial autobiography, Mamphela Ramphele: A Life, to critically reflect on what the actions of “non-subservient Blackwomen” reveal about the lived experience of being Black and a woman under Apartheid South Africa.The article by Siseko Kumalo infuses decolonial and literary criticism as projects that may allow for a recognition of the “ontological legitimacy” of amaqaba (those who rejected colonial influences and education). Through a close reading of S. E. K. Mqhayi’s Intshayelelo: Imbali, the article engages with the question How does a model of inclusive national identity in South Africa, once established, get us to the point of recognition for the Indigene?
特邀编辑简介
本期特刊正值非洲国家和全球南方国家在获取能源以推动其经济发展方面面临前所未有的危机之际。西方发达国家对发展中国家施加了巨大的权力和压力,要求它们放弃化石燃料,与此同时,西方国家也在增加对化石燃料的吸收,这在很大程度上导致了危机的发生。然而,通过批判性的自我反省,我们能够理解,这种性质的危机并非没有历史先例,因为在它之前,对以前和仍然被殖民的人民施加了一系列其他形式的不公正。不久前,COVID-19在卫生领域的大流行及其处理表明,世界仍然是多么的扭曲和分裂,并暴露了地方和全球层面的种族不平等。因此,可以肯定的是,当前的危机是反对基于种族的社会不公正的斗争历史的一部分,并表明西方希望继续对其前殖民地进行控制。尽管能源转型被称为“公平的能源转型”,但对于那些受到负面影响的发展中国家来说,显然没有什么“公平”可言。因此,虽然我们通常倾向于谈论社会或历史的不公正,如能源危机和COVID-19,但在认识论方面,我们发现了认知上的不公正。因此,本期的文章有助于反殖民运动(广义上的)对不公正的一系列回应,特别是在殖民者和被殖民者、中心和边缘之间的关系中,它对知识和知识生产的认识论影响。此外,历史上将非洲和其他非欧洲民族从理性的参与中排除在外的结果是,非洲人尤其被排除在哲学本身之外,这是非洲哲学和相关学科今天仍在学术界努力解决的现象。总而言之,这些文章做出了重要的贡献,因为它们考虑到了种族和种族主义的历史对哲学的影响,尤其是作为一门学科和人类精神活动的影响。应该记住,将非洲人排除在理性之外,并最终排除在哲学之外,在此之前有一个更早的先例,即将非洲人排除在人类层面的承认之外,即将非洲人排除在理性存在之外。我们可以说这是一段去人格化和去人性化的历史;被压迫者因殖民遭遇而遭受的屠杀和掠夺。这就是为什么对于一个边缘的学者和哲学家来说,用恩里克·杜塞尔的话来说,哲学探究不能也不应该脱离人类现实。事实上,外围学者经常强调哲学不能过分抽象现实;哲学也应该把自己局限于人类解放的目的。有很多边缘国家的思想家都以反复强调这一点而闻名。例如,刘易斯·戈登(Lewis Gordon)引入了“学科颓废”(discipline decadence)的概念,通过这个概念,他哀叹对方法的拜物教,以及学科本身成为目的,因此不一定能满足人类的需求。这一学派的其他思想家包括恩里克·杜塞尔、查尔斯·米尔斯、康奈尔·韦斯特、安吉拉·戴维斯和乔治·扬西等人,仅举几例。扬西谈到了"密度计划"他对黑人哲学家有一个规范的禁令。类似地,杜塞尔在《解放哲学》中评论说:“哲学,当它是真正的哲学而不是诡辩或意识形态时,不思考哲学。它不思考哲学文本,除了作为一个教学宣传提供自己的解释范畴。哲学思考非哲学的东西;现实。这种现实,正如人们所断言的那样,在存在主义现象学中,不仅仅是客观的现实,或者可能是自发存在的东西,而是让-保罗·萨特与“人类现实”联系在一起的东西,这是有血有肉的人所生活的现实。因此,在一个被划分为中心与边缘、人类与次等、白人与黑人的世界里,反殖民主义思想家不能不提出与社会存在有关的问题,即“现实”。因此,对于那些在学术界的人来说,一个人必须能够接受非西方和“非科学知识”(以Boaventura De Sousa Santos命名)不被认为是可信的知识的现实,以及被遗忘的可能性,被完全从历史中抹去的可能性。正如我们在伯纳德·马托利诺的文章中所看到的,这是非洲哲学在过去的二三十年里积极应对的一场战斗。 在西方正典中,哲学一般被认为是从希腊人开始的,正如我们所观察到的,这不是历史上的偶然,而是将以前的哲学传统贬低到相对默默无闻的计划的一部分,并将人类的其余部分排除在理性之外。其理念是,为了使西方现代性成为一个可行的项目,受压迫的文化必须出于必要而拒绝理性。在这一点上,弗朗茨·法农在《黑皮肤白面具》中这样评论道:“(理性战线上的)胜利是猫捉老鼠;这使我出丑了。正如另一位所说,当我在场的时候,它不是;当它在那里的时候,我已经不在了。在这方面,Mogobe Ramose的文章指出,亚里士多德关于人是一种理性动物的概念,就与黑人有关而言,是如何成为一种用词不当的。有了这种手法,以前的文明,如非洲(埃及)和阿拉伯的哲学传统,就应该从历史和认识论的视野中消失。在这方面,米尔斯的真知灼见将在他去世后的很长一段时间里继续困扰着哲学界。米尔斯注意到,在西方化的大学里,一个典型的哲学课程通常会从两位希腊哲学家柏拉图和亚里士多德开始。从这里开始,它涵盖了中世纪,并可能以自由主义理论结束。尽管这一时期涵盖了两千多年的西方哲学史,但很少或根本没有提到在希腊人之前形成哲学思想的传统。尽管如此,本期的文章表明,非洲人和被压迫人民不仅具有反思的理性,而且还具有独特的哲学。总的来说,这些文章不仅肯定了非洲哲学的认识论立场,而且展示了它自己的谱系、话语和目标。通过这些简短的评论,下面的文章跨越了这些主题领域:种族形而上学、认识论的种族主义、种族本体论、女权主义和非殖民化文学。因此,Bernard Matolino的这篇文章首先深入研究了种族的形而上学,并指出尽管没有证据表明存在不同的种族(在Kwame Appiah之后),种族作为社会生活的一个问题是活生生的和相关的。此外,他的文章继续展示了非洲哲学如何成为一种抗议形式,以及土著哲学家需要证明土著人民总是有一种哲学。同样,Edwin Etieyibo的文章也讨论了认识论上的种族主义,以及肤色偏见在历史上是如何转化为其他形式的种族不公正的,比如认识论上的种族主义。他的文章利用了像阿尼巴尔·基哈诺和拉蒙·格罗弗格尔这样的思想家的作品来追溯现代这种不公正的谱系。Siphiwe Ndlovu的文章探讨了黑人边缘化问题,特别是在现代时期。他将自己的思考定位在社会契约传统中,但通过米尔斯的种族契约,他提出了一种对当代边缘化的解读。因此,这篇文章并没有把黑人边缘化看作是被排斥或被排除在契约之外的结果,而是认为这种边缘化不是由于被排斥本身,而是由于被纳入,尽管只是作为种族契约中较低级的——因此也就是较低级的——伙伴。Mogobe Ramose的文章首先赞同Kwasi Wiredu的观点,即非洲哲学专注于与非非洲哲学不完全相同的问题并没有错。此外,他的文章通过d.m. Goldenberg追溯了反黑人种族主义的根源,从古典世界阿拉伯人的“颜色象征主义”,到拉比时代,再到后来以种族偏见的形式出现在基督教中。他文章的核心论点是,将人类分裂成多个碎片的普遍做法违背了对人类关系中正义与和平的追求。Zinhle ka’nobuhlaluse的文章将Anika Mann关于种族和女权主义的观点作为存在主义的立场和基础。她拿起曼菲拉·兰菲尔的第一本自传《曼菲拉·兰菲尔:一生》,批判性地反思“不服从的黑人妇女”的行为揭示了南非种族隔离下黑人和女性的生活经历。Siseko Kumalo的文章注入了非殖民化和文学批评,作为项目,可能允许承认amaqaba(那些拒绝殖民影响和教育的人)的“本体论合法性”。通过仔细阅读s.e.k. Mqhayi的《Intshayelelo: Imbali》,本文探讨了这样一个问题:在南非,包容性的民族认同模式一旦建立,如何让我们认识到土著人?
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
求助全文
约1分钟内获得全文 求助全文
来源期刊
Critical Philosophy of Race
Critical Philosophy of Race ETHNIC STUDIES-
CiteScore
2.30
自引率
0.00%
发文量
16
期刊介绍: The critical philosophy of race consists in the philosophical examination of issues raised by the concept of race, the practices and mechanisms of racialization, and the persistence of various forms of racism across the world. Critical philosophy of race is a critical enterprise in three respects: it opposes racism in all its forms; it rejects the pseudosciences of old-fashioned biological racialism; and it denies that anti-racism and anti-racialism summarily eliminate race as a meaningful category of analysis. Critical philosophy of race is a philosophical enterprise because of its engagement with traditional philosophical questions and in its readiness to engage critically some of the traditional answers.
文献相关原料
公司名称 产品信息 采购帮参考价格
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
确定
请完成安全验证×
copy
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
右上角分享
点击右上角分享
0
联系我们:info@booksci.cn Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。 Copyright © 2023 布克学术 All rights reserved.
京ICP备2023020795号-1
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术官方微信