Human Evolution and Fantastic Victorian Fiction

IF 0.5 2区 文学 0 LANGUAGE & LINGUISTICS
STYLE Pub Date : 2023-11-01 DOI:10.5325/style.57.4.0525
Emelie Jonsson
{"title":"Human Evolution and Fantastic Victorian Fiction","authors":"Emelie Jonsson","doi":"10.5325/style.57.4.0525","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"Anna Neill’s Human Evolution and Fantastic Victorian Fiction is bound to have different effects depending on who opens it. If the reader is an average literary scholar with an interest in science, the book will produce the warm fuzziness of familiar ideas unfolding familiarly. If the reader is an average historian of science, some puzzlement may occur about the presumed central role of literature, but the book’s pattern will be unsurprising. If the reader is a biologist or an evolutionary social scientist, the experience may resemble Neill’s citation of Samuel Butler’s hypothetical “grain of corn in the hen’s stomach,” which “finds itself in an environment so unfamiliar to the world its forefathers have taught it to navigate, that it ceases to remember it is grain” (97). If the reader is a literary scholar who believes in the epistemological validity of science, there might be neither surprise nor fuzziness. The present reader responded with mild fatigue when Butler, sentient grains and all, was placed next to Darwin and described as a “genius” (95).Neill’s book fits safely within literary study’s current program for interpreting evolutionary theory in nineteenth-century literature. I have characterized that program at length elsewhere, identifying its core tenets and tracing its roots to the early 1980s (Jonsson, “Old Tune” and Early Evolutionary Imagination 74–87). I argued that Gillian Beer’s Darwin’s Plots (first published in 1983) established parameters that largely remain in place for present scholars: a tendency to treat evolutionary theory as semi-fictional, a tendency to suggest that evolutionary theory owes more to literary inspiration than to scientific methodology, and a tendency to view any epistemological validity in evolutionary theory as a confirmation of literary theories popularized around the 1980s—deconstructive indeterminacy of meaning; the cultural construction of (human) nature; and the consequent vilification of hierarchies, definitions, and noncultural explanations. In line with the idea that meaning is indeterminate, Beer employed techniques of argumentation that simultaneously advance and withdraw claims (evolution both is and is not fictional), avoiding accusations of anti-scientific rhetoric (Jonsson, Early Evolutionary Imagination 74–87). The resulting program opens up a world of possibilities for reading and rereading novels with different degrees of emphasis on indeterminacy and hierarchies. It also prevents interdisciplinary understanding, feeds academic territorialism, encourages ideological distortion, and leads scholars in circles of repetition toward sheer stagnation. In my view, this program has stymied the study of a deeply fascinating subject for forty years.Neill indicates that no change is in sight. If anything, the slimness of her book and the meekness of its argument suggest some petering out of the program. Fantastic Victorian Fiction spends its conclusion—traditionally a place for extending and rhetorically elevating one’s claims—on a brief gesture to the more fashionable genre of twenty-first-century “indigenous futurisms” (148). Neill herself seems genuinely interested in her nineteenth-century subject. She delves into the biographical and historical context of each author and displays some imaginative immersion in each literary text. This is particularly remarkable given the abstract and didactic nature of some of her texts, like Flatland and The Water-Babies. Nevertheless, she seems unable to explain the interest of her subject, or even to articulate it, beyond tired formulas about Victorian racism, classism, and sexism. Those formulas lead her in the iron circles of a carousel, from foregone conclusion to illusory revelation. The details of her significantly different literary texts all reduce to the claim that they use wild and unpredictable ideas of evolution to challenge a racist, classist, and sexist idea of evolution. That challenge is implicitly what makes the literary texts interesting or worthy of explanation.Fantastic Victorian Fiction does not convincingly explain its literary selection, though it advertises it in the title. A naïve scholar setting out to study evolution in fantastic literature might choose texts that are straightforwardly influenced by evolutionary theory and classified as fantastic. Someone familiar with this forty-year program will know that the focus is numinous cultural effects rather than demonstrable influence—indeed, that demonstrable influence was somewhat scorned by its pioneers (Jonsson, Early Evolutionary Imagination 77–78). With due numinousness, Neill moves from Charles Kingsley and Lewis Carroll to Rudyard Kipling, H. G. Wells, Samuel Butler, Edwin Abbott Abbott, Edward Bellamy, and William Morris. Only three of these eight authors (Kingsley, Butler, and Wells) were directly concerned with evolution. One is American rather than Victorian. All of them can be described as “fantastic” in the sense that they depict counterintuitive realities and tend more or less toward symbolism and allegory, but so could any number of other Victorian authors—George MacDonald, Bram Stoker, Oscar Wilde, Arthur Machen, or Sheridan Le Fanu. One might think that a general interest in science determines the selection, but that is not born out by Bellamy or Morris—and would have been true of the excluded Stoker. Kipling is a stretch in that respect too, though the case could have been made more robust by his handful of speculative fiction stories. Instead, he is included for his Just So Stories, which imitate oral storytelling in a manner that supposedly elevates the “savage” practices deplored by the version of evolutionary history that Neill opposes: “an often pernicious evolutionary conception of the human” (2). Carroll is similarly included because his interest in and supposedly sympathetic depictions of mental illness elevates the mentally ill. Abbott’s Flatland is mainly concerned with mathematics, but he was interested in pedagogy and can thus be said to comment on human development. Three of the texts (by Wells, Bellamy, and Morris) are included because they are socialist utopias, though only one of the authors was influenced by evolution.One needs a vast net to catch these texts together. As Neill puts it, they are “on the face of it, a motley collection” (7). Through this admission, she acknowledges—perhaps semi-consciously—that her scholarly program does not offer adequate guidance or justification for a literary selection. Her texts are united only by her claim that they oppose an evil version of evolution—but that claim, too, is heavily qualified. According to Neill, her literary texts remain “embroiled” to different degrees in precisely the pernicious version of evolution that she opposes, so that she cannot “ignore those surface depictions” that apparently contradict her argument about the authors’ ideological affiliations (10). One is left wondering whether it was necessary to involve evolution. The real thesis formula seems to be the one that literary scholars imbibe from their undergraduate years: “Is this text sexist, racist, or otherwise discriminatory?” with the illuminating (and invariable) answer “Yes and no.”Literary scholars who write about evolutionary theory still tend, like Beer, to obscure their claims with dense terminology that is juggled in precise movements of distraction. Neill is less guilty of this than other recent contributors to the field (see Duncan; Griffiths), but she nevertheless operates within a field that is built on equivocation. It is simply more convincing to say that Samuel Butler is an important evolutionary thinker if you say it obscurely. Similarly, it is more convincing to say that “these texts all in different ways wrench human development out of deep, gradual time” than to say that a set of literary works liberate humans from their evolutionary past (10). If Neill were challenged with the plain version of this claim, she might explain that she meant that these literary works free us from a particular interpretation of the evolutionary past—a narrative about evolutionary history that stresses “deep, gradual time.” But, you might say, is it not unavoidable to stress deep time and gradualism when discussing evolutionary history? In response, Neill could specify (as she does elsewhere) that she meant a gradualist narrative about deep time that is teleological, anthropocentric, and insistent on discriminatory hierarchies. These ideas are not implied by the word gradualism. Before you can accuse Neill of redefining that word, however, she qualifies conscientiously: “not to suggest that the (gradualist) theory of evolution . . . was inherently racist” (3, italics in original). If pressed very hard, she might even admit that she was only talking about what the literary texts depict or suggest imaginatively, not what they change in the real world. None of these specifics or qualifications are there to disturb the thrilling suggestion that our species can be freed (“wrenched away”) from deep time and gradualism by reading The Island of Dr. Moreau. Even as an afficionado of Wells, I would object to that estimation of his bio-transformative powers.Rhetoric of the nature just described can be confusing to readers who are unfamiliar with it. It can be confusing, in a different way, to readers who are so familiar with it that it has become second nature. To clarify my point, here is a translation into plain language of the forty-year program within which Neill operates—a narrative of evolutionary history, as it were, with literature in a leading role:This interpretive pattern can be altered to make Darwin more or less of a villain and to further emphasize the importance of literature. For instance, Devin Griffiths argued that Darwin’s theory was highly inspired by the historical fiction of Walter Scott (Jonsson, “Old Tune”). Neill adds very little to the pattern. She portrays her authors as torn between evil hierarchies and liberating chaos. She focuses on “fantastic fiction,” but her argument about the genre precisely resembles arguments about other genres aligned with liberating chaos (from novels to “weird realism” to historical fiction) (Levine; Duncan; Griffiths). She is particularly concerned with the perniciousness of “gradualism” and “Malthusianism,” but that perniciousness was noted by literary scholars in the 1980s who preferred to focus on Aristotelian essentialism or literary realism—all of which translate more or less directly into evil, in alliance with categorization and human nature, and thus supposedly with sexism and racism (Beer; Levine).Neill herself is rather modest in her invocation of this mythic clash between good and evil, but she pays full respects to the less modest luminaries of the field, from Gillian Beer and George Levine to Deleuze, Guattari, and Derrida (1–2, 42, 89, 90, 96, 101). She is unwaveringly loyal to the program, despite her plentiful qualifications. Most overtly, she joins Deleuze and Guattari in celebrating Samuel Butler as a prescient thinker who would “surely have been gratified” that “many of his claims now resonate with posthumanist challenges” (96). This account of Butler’s “combination of Lamarckian evolution and associationist psychology” is maintained against the historical derision of evolutionary biologists (99). More amusingly, it is maintained against Butler’s own local admission that his ideas do not make “the smallest pretension to scientific value,” instead intending to “entertain and instruct the numerous class of people who . . . enjoy speculating and reflecting (not too deeply) on the phenomena around them” (99). In Neill’s view, this is Butler’s way of stressing the vital importance of literature: “he seemed to say that science must become more like popular fiction if it is to open minds to truly new ideas” (99). Moments like this could make anyone feel like a grain of corn in a hen’s stomach. One minute we are reflecting on the imaginative effects of the greatest paradigm shift in biology, the next we are soberly bid to consider Derrida’s thoughts as he stood naked before his cat (90). Apparently, in this world of avian digestion, “Darwin is often seen as a precursor to Deleuze and Guattari” (92). In such a world, we might as well be asked to believe that literature is crucial to science on the word of a literary scholar interpreting a novelist.I don’t pretend to know how earnestly Neill believes in the program that structures her book or the formulas that shape her literary interpretations. She often seems to forget about both program and formulas as she produces competent historical exposition or lively plot summary. Her description of Abbott’s ideal of liberal education, for instance, is delightful (113–117). She is charmingly responsive to the craftsmanship of William Morris and the Tristram Shandy-like material humor of Abbott (whose perfectly square book and sloppy geometrical drawings are depicted in illustrations). At other times, she seems almost embarrassed by her chosen literary texts. In the brief conclusion, after discussing the importance of recent works by indigenous authors Louise Erdrich and Cherie Dimaline, Neill all but apologizes for her choice: “My Victorian texts are quite different, of course. They are all written by professional, middle-class (and with one exception) British men during the height of empire” (149). One might question whether these are the most significant differences between, say, the novels of Erdrich and those of Wells. More to the point, one might question the implicit evaluation of the past through the degree to which it resembles the present. While it is admirable to champion the downtrodden and connect historical novels to modern concerns, it is a very Victorian fallacy (that Neill claims to oppose) to consider one’s own moral values the culmination of history. My hope is that she is more earnest in her imaginative immersion than in her apologies.It seems doubtful that Neill’s book represents the last gasps of literary study’s program for nineteenth-century depictions of evolution. High-profile monographs by Duncan and Griffiths are just a few years old, and more are likely to appear. However, Neill’s enactment of a waning moon is cause for reflection. Her book is essentially a slim collection of thematic summaries, written in a lively voice and replete with historical detail, but run through a filter of weak formulas and preconceptions that place every bit of information in doubt. What would it mean to lose such books? I cannot say whether it is better to convey literary history in distorted morsels than to leave it to oblivion. But I also don’t think those are the two alternatives. Neill’s subject has inherent interest, and so do (at least some of) the texts she treats. This piece of literary history will most likely keep being pursued by inquisitive minds. It would only be a good thing for a stagnant, distorting program to make room for more vigorous alternatives—alternatives that could perhaps aim to advance knowledge about nineteenth-century literature instead of measuring it with ideological formulas. A new program might use a current understanding of evolutionary biology to frame Victorian ideas, acknowledging the reality of both the struggle for life and human social adaptations; it might use information about basic human motives, cognitive biases, and the adaptive function of the imagination to explain why evolutionary theory tends to be reshaped into certain types of myths; and it might add personality psychology to biographical research in order to tease out how and why individual authors turned evolution into particular stories (Jonsson, Early Evolutionary Imagination). Perhaps Neill, too, would benefit from such change.","PeriodicalId":45300,"journal":{"name":"STYLE","volume":"24 3","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.5000,"publicationDate":"2023-11-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":"0","resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"STYLE","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.5325/style.57.4.0525","RegionNum":2,"RegionCategory":"文学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"0","JCRName":"LANGUAGE & LINGUISTICS","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0

Abstract

Anna Neill’s Human Evolution and Fantastic Victorian Fiction is bound to have different effects depending on who opens it. If the reader is an average literary scholar with an interest in science, the book will produce the warm fuzziness of familiar ideas unfolding familiarly. If the reader is an average historian of science, some puzzlement may occur about the presumed central role of literature, but the book’s pattern will be unsurprising. If the reader is a biologist or an evolutionary social scientist, the experience may resemble Neill’s citation of Samuel Butler’s hypothetical “grain of corn in the hen’s stomach,” which “finds itself in an environment so unfamiliar to the world its forefathers have taught it to navigate, that it ceases to remember it is grain” (97). If the reader is a literary scholar who believes in the epistemological validity of science, there might be neither surprise nor fuzziness. The present reader responded with mild fatigue when Butler, sentient grains and all, was placed next to Darwin and described as a “genius” (95).Neill’s book fits safely within literary study’s current program for interpreting evolutionary theory in nineteenth-century literature. I have characterized that program at length elsewhere, identifying its core tenets and tracing its roots to the early 1980s (Jonsson, “Old Tune” and Early Evolutionary Imagination 74–87). I argued that Gillian Beer’s Darwin’s Plots (first published in 1983) established parameters that largely remain in place for present scholars: a tendency to treat evolutionary theory as semi-fictional, a tendency to suggest that evolutionary theory owes more to literary inspiration than to scientific methodology, and a tendency to view any epistemological validity in evolutionary theory as a confirmation of literary theories popularized around the 1980s—deconstructive indeterminacy of meaning; the cultural construction of (human) nature; and the consequent vilification of hierarchies, definitions, and noncultural explanations. In line with the idea that meaning is indeterminate, Beer employed techniques of argumentation that simultaneously advance and withdraw claims (evolution both is and is not fictional), avoiding accusations of anti-scientific rhetoric (Jonsson, Early Evolutionary Imagination 74–87). The resulting program opens up a world of possibilities for reading and rereading novels with different degrees of emphasis on indeterminacy and hierarchies. It also prevents interdisciplinary understanding, feeds academic territorialism, encourages ideological distortion, and leads scholars in circles of repetition toward sheer stagnation. In my view, this program has stymied the study of a deeply fascinating subject for forty years.Neill indicates that no change is in sight. If anything, the slimness of her book and the meekness of its argument suggest some petering out of the program. Fantastic Victorian Fiction spends its conclusion—traditionally a place for extending and rhetorically elevating one’s claims—on a brief gesture to the more fashionable genre of twenty-first-century “indigenous futurisms” (148). Neill herself seems genuinely interested in her nineteenth-century subject. She delves into the biographical and historical context of each author and displays some imaginative immersion in each literary text. This is particularly remarkable given the abstract and didactic nature of some of her texts, like Flatland and The Water-Babies. Nevertheless, she seems unable to explain the interest of her subject, or even to articulate it, beyond tired formulas about Victorian racism, classism, and sexism. Those formulas lead her in the iron circles of a carousel, from foregone conclusion to illusory revelation. The details of her significantly different literary texts all reduce to the claim that they use wild and unpredictable ideas of evolution to challenge a racist, classist, and sexist idea of evolution. That challenge is implicitly what makes the literary texts interesting or worthy of explanation.Fantastic Victorian Fiction does not convincingly explain its literary selection, though it advertises it in the title. A naïve scholar setting out to study evolution in fantastic literature might choose texts that are straightforwardly influenced by evolutionary theory and classified as fantastic. Someone familiar with this forty-year program will know that the focus is numinous cultural effects rather than demonstrable influence—indeed, that demonstrable influence was somewhat scorned by its pioneers (Jonsson, Early Evolutionary Imagination 77–78). With due numinousness, Neill moves from Charles Kingsley and Lewis Carroll to Rudyard Kipling, H. G. Wells, Samuel Butler, Edwin Abbott Abbott, Edward Bellamy, and William Morris. Only three of these eight authors (Kingsley, Butler, and Wells) were directly concerned with evolution. One is American rather than Victorian. All of them can be described as “fantastic” in the sense that they depict counterintuitive realities and tend more or less toward symbolism and allegory, but so could any number of other Victorian authors—George MacDonald, Bram Stoker, Oscar Wilde, Arthur Machen, or Sheridan Le Fanu. One might think that a general interest in science determines the selection, but that is not born out by Bellamy or Morris—and would have been true of the excluded Stoker. Kipling is a stretch in that respect too, though the case could have been made more robust by his handful of speculative fiction stories. Instead, he is included for his Just So Stories, which imitate oral storytelling in a manner that supposedly elevates the “savage” practices deplored by the version of evolutionary history that Neill opposes: “an often pernicious evolutionary conception of the human” (2). Carroll is similarly included because his interest in and supposedly sympathetic depictions of mental illness elevates the mentally ill. Abbott’s Flatland is mainly concerned with mathematics, but he was interested in pedagogy and can thus be said to comment on human development. Three of the texts (by Wells, Bellamy, and Morris) are included because they are socialist utopias, though only one of the authors was influenced by evolution.One needs a vast net to catch these texts together. As Neill puts it, they are “on the face of it, a motley collection” (7). Through this admission, she acknowledges—perhaps semi-consciously—that her scholarly program does not offer adequate guidance or justification for a literary selection. Her texts are united only by her claim that they oppose an evil version of evolution—but that claim, too, is heavily qualified. According to Neill, her literary texts remain “embroiled” to different degrees in precisely the pernicious version of evolution that she opposes, so that she cannot “ignore those surface depictions” that apparently contradict her argument about the authors’ ideological affiliations (10). One is left wondering whether it was necessary to involve evolution. The real thesis formula seems to be the one that literary scholars imbibe from their undergraduate years: “Is this text sexist, racist, or otherwise discriminatory?” with the illuminating (and invariable) answer “Yes and no.”Literary scholars who write about evolutionary theory still tend, like Beer, to obscure their claims with dense terminology that is juggled in precise movements of distraction. Neill is less guilty of this than other recent contributors to the field (see Duncan; Griffiths), but she nevertheless operates within a field that is built on equivocation. It is simply more convincing to say that Samuel Butler is an important evolutionary thinker if you say it obscurely. Similarly, it is more convincing to say that “these texts all in different ways wrench human development out of deep, gradual time” than to say that a set of literary works liberate humans from their evolutionary past (10). If Neill were challenged with the plain version of this claim, she might explain that she meant that these literary works free us from a particular interpretation of the evolutionary past—a narrative about evolutionary history that stresses “deep, gradual time.” But, you might say, is it not unavoidable to stress deep time and gradualism when discussing evolutionary history? In response, Neill could specify (as she does elsewhere) that she meant a gradualist narrative about deep time that is teleological, anthropocentric, and insistent on discriminatory hierarchies. These ideas are not implied by the word gradualism. Before you can accuse Neill of redefining that word, however, she qualifies conscientiously: “not to suggest that the (gradualist) theory of evolution . . . was inherently racist” (3, italics in original). If pressed very hard, she might even admit that she was only talking about what the literary texts depict or suggest imaginatively, not what they change in the real world. None of these specifics or qualifications are there to disturb the thrilling suggestion that our species can be freed (“wrenched away”) from deep time and gradualism by reading The Island of Dr. Moreau. Even as an afficionado of Wells, I would object to that estimation of his bio-transformative powers.Rhetoric of the nature just described can be confusing to readers who are unfamiliar with it. It can be confusing, in a different way, to readers who are so familiar with it that it has become second nature. To clarify my point, here is a translation into plain language of the forty-year program within which Neill operates—a narrative of evolutionary history, as it were, with literature in a leading role:This interpretive pattern can be altered to make Darwin more or less of a villain and to further emphasize the importance of literature. For instance, Devin Griffiths argued that Darwin’s theory was highly inspired by the historical fiction of Walter Scott (Jonsson, “Old Tune”). Neill adds very little to the pattern. She portrays her authors as torn between evil hierarchies and liberating chaos. She focuses on “fantastic fiction,” but her argument about the genre precisely resembles arguments about other genres aligned with liberating chaos (from novels to “weird realism” to historical fiction) (Levine; Duncan; Griffiths). She is particularly concerned with the perniciousness of “gradualism” and “Malthusianism,” but that perniciousness was noted by literary scholars in the 1980s who preferred to focus on Aristotelian essentialism or literary realism—all of which translate more or less directly into evil, in alliance with categorization and human nature, and thus supposedly with sexism and racism (Beer; Levine).Neill herself is rather modest in her invocation of this mythic clash between good and evil, but she pays full respects to the less modest luminaries of the field, from Gillian Beer and George Levine to Deleuze, Guattari, and Derrida (1–2, 42, 89, 90, 96, 101). She is unwaveringly loyal to the program, despite her plentiful qualifications. Most overtly, she joins Deleuze and Guattari in celebrating Samuel Butler as a prescient thinker who would “surely have been gratified” that “many of his claims now resonate with posthumanist challenges” (96). This account of Butler’s “combination of Lamarckian evolution and associationist psychology” is maintained against the historical derision of evolutionary biologists (99). More amusingly, it is maintained against Butler’s own local admission that his ideas do not make “the smallest pretension to scientific value,” instead intending to “entertain and instruct the numerous class of people who . . . enjoy speculating and reflecting (not too deeply) on the phenomena around them” (99). In Neill’s view, this is Butler’s way of stressing the vital importance of literature: “he seemed to say that science must become more like popular fiction if it is to open minds to truly new ideas” (99). Moments like this could make anyone feel like a grain of corn in a hen’s stomach. One minute we are reflecting on the imaginative effects of the greatest paradigm shift in biology, the next we are soberly bid to consider Derrida’s thoughts as he stood naked before his cat (90). Apparently, in this world of avian digestion, “Darwin is often seen as a precursor to Deleuze and Guattari” (92). In such a world, we might as well be asked to believe that literature is crucial to science on the word of a literary scholar interpreting a novelist.I don’t pretend to know how earnestly Neill believes in the program that structures her book or the formulas that shape her literary interpretations. She often seems to forget about both program and formulas as she produces competent historical exposition or lively plot summary. Her description of Abbott’s ideal of liberal education, for instance, is delightful (113–117). She is charmingly responsive to the craftsmanship of William Morris and the Tristram Shandy-like material humor of Abbott (whose perfectly square book and sloppy geometrical drawings are depicted in illustrations). At other times, she seems almost embarrassed by her chosen literary texts. In the brief conclusion, after discussing the importance of recent works by indigenous authors Louise Erdrich and Cherie Dimaline, Neill all but apologizes for her choice: “My Victorian texts are quite different, of course. They are all written by professional, middle-class (and with one exception) British men during the height of empire” (149). One might question whether these are the most significant differences between, say, the novels of Erdrich and those of Wells. More to the point, one might question the implicit evaluation of the past through the degree to which it resembles the present. While it is admirable to champion the downtrodden and connect historical novels to modern concerns, it is a very Victorian fallacy (that Neill claims to oppose) to consider one’s own moral values the culmination of history. My hope is that she is more earnest in her imaginative immersion than in her apologies.It seems doubtful that Neill’s book represents the last gasps of literary study’s program for nineteenth-century depictions of evolution. High-profile monographs by Duncan and Griffiths are just a few years old, and more are likely to appear. However, Neill’s enactment of a waning moon is cause for reflection. Her book is essentially a slim collection of thematic summaries, written in a lively voice and replete with historical detail, but run through a filter of weak formulas and preconceptions that place every bit of information in doubt. What would it mean to lose such books? I cannot say whether it is better to convey literary history in distorted morsels than to leave it to oblivion. But I also don’t think those are the two alternatives. Neill’s subject has inherent interest, and so do (at least some of) the texts she treats. This piece of literary history will most likely keep being pursued by inquisitive minds. It would only be a good thing for a stagnant, distorting program to make room for more vigorous alternatives—alternatives that could perhaps aim to advance knowledge about nineteenth-century literature instead of measuring it with ideological formulas. A new program might use a current understanding of evolutionary biology to frame Victorian ideas, acknowledging the reality of both the struggle for life and human social adaptations; it might use information about basic human motives, cognitive biases, and the adaptive function of the imagination to explain why evolutionary theory tends to be reshaped into certain types of myths; and it might add personality psychology to biographical research in order to tease out how and why individual authors turned evolution into particular stories (Jonsson, Early Evolutionary Imagination). Perhaps Neill, too, would benefit from such change.
人类进化与维多利亚时代的奇幻小说
安娜·尼尔的《人类进化与维多利亚时代的奇幻小说》必然会产生不同的效果,这取决于谁打开它。如果读者是一个对科学感兴趣的普通文学学者,这本书将产生熟悉的概念在熟悉的情况下展开的温暖的模糊感。如果读者是一个普通的科学历史学家,可能会对文学的假定中心作用产生一些困惑,但这本书的模式并不令人惊讶。如果读者是生物学家或进化社会科学家,这种经历可能类似于尼尔引用塞缪尔·巴特勒(Samuel Butler)假设的“母鸡胃里的谷粒”,“母鸡发现自己置身于一个对它的祖先教给它如何导航的世界如此陌生的环境中,以至于它不再记得自己是谷粒”(97)。如果读者是一位相信科学的认识论有效性的文学学者,那么就既不会感到惊讶,也不会感到模糊。当巴特勒,有知觉的谷物和所有的一切,被放在达尔文旁边,并被称为“天才”时,现在的读者的反应是轻微的疲劳。尼尔的书完全符合当前文学研究中解释19世纪文学进化理论的项目。我在其他地方详细描述了这个项目,确定了它的核心原则,并将其根源追溯到20世纪80年代初(Jonsson,“Old Tune”和早期进化想象74-87)。我认为吉莉安·比尔(Gillian Beer)的《达尔文的故事》(Darwin’s Plots, 1983年首次出版)建立的参数在很大程度上仍然适用于现在的学者:一种将进化论视为半虚构的倾向,一种认为进化论更多地归功于文学灵感而不是科学方法论的倾向,一种将进化论的任何认识论有效性视为对20世纪80年代前后流行的文学理论的确认的倾向——解构主义意义的不确定性;人性的文化建构;以及随之而来的对等级制度、定义和非文化解释的诋毁。与意义是不确定的观点一致,比尔采用了同时推进和撤回主张的论证技术(进化既不是虚构的,也不是虚构的),避免了反科学修辞的指责(Jonsson,早期进化想象74-87)。由此产生的程序为阅读和重读不同程度强调不确定性和等级的小说开辟了一个可能性的世界。它还阻碍了跨学科的理解,助长了学术领域主义,鼓励了意识形态的扭曲,并导致学者们在重复的圈子里走向完全的停滞。在我看来,这个项目阻碍了对一个极具吸引力的学科的研究长达40年之久。尼尔表示,目前还看不到任何变化。如果说有什么不同的话,那就是她的书很薄,其论点也很温和,这表明这个项目正在逐渐淡出。《维多利亚时代的奇幻小说》的结尾——传统上是一个延伸和修辞提升一个人的主张的地方——对21世纪更流行的“本土未来主义”流派做了一个简短的姿态。尼尔本人似乎对她的十九世纪主题真的很感兴趣。她深入研究了每位作者的传记和历史背景,并在每个文学文本中展示了一些富有想象力的沉浸感。考虑到她的一些作品的抽象和说教性质,比如《平地》和《水娃》,这一点尤其引人注目。然而,她似乎无法解释她的主题的兴趣,甚至无法表达出来,除了关于维多利亚时代的种族主义、阶级歧视和性别歧视的陈词滥调。这些公式把她带进旋转木马的铁圈里,从既定的结论到虚幻的启示。她那些截然不同的文学作品的细节都可以归结为,这些作品都是用野蛮和不可预测的进化论来挑战种族主义、阶级主义和性别歧视的进化论。这种挑战是文学文本有趣或值得解释的隐含原因。《维多利亚梦幻小说》并没有令人信服地解释它的文学选择,尽管它在标题中做了宣传。一位naïve学者打算在奇幻文学中研究进化论,他可能会选择直接受进化论影响并被归类为奇幻文学的文本。熟悉这个四十年项目的人会知道,重点是神秘的文化影响,而不是显而易见的影响——事实上,这种显而易见的影响在某种程度上被它的先驱者所蔑视(Jonsson,早期进化想象77-78)。从查尔斯·金斯利和刘易斯·卡罗尔,到拉迪亚德·吉卜林、h·g·威尔斯、塞缪尔·巴特勒、埃德温·阿伯特·阿伯特、爱德华·贝拉米和威廉·莫里斯,尼尔的作品都有了应有的知名度。这8位作者中只有3位(金斯利、巴特勒和威尔斯)直接与进化论有关。一个是美国人,而不是维多利亚人。 尼尔对这种模式的补充很少。她把她的作者描绘成在邪恶的等级制度和解放的混乱之间挣扎的人。她关注的是“奇幻小说”,但她对这种类型的观点与对其他类型的观点完全相似,这些类型都与解放混乱(从小说到“怪异现实主义”再到历史小说)有关。邓肯;Griffiths)。她特别关注“渐进主义”和“马尔萨斯主义”的危害性,但这种危害性在20世纪80年代被文学学者注意到,他们更倾向于关注亚里士多德的本质主义或文学现实主义——所有这些都或多或少直接转化为邪恶,与分类和人性结盟,因此被认为与性别歧视和种族主义(比尔;Levine)。尼尔本人在提到这种神话般的善恶冲突时相当谦虚,但她对这个领域中不那么谦虚的杰出人物表示了充分的敬意,从吉莉安·比尔和乔治·莱文到德勒兹、瓜塔里和德里达(1 - 2,42,89,90,96,101)。她坚定不移地忠于这个项目,尽管她资历丰富。最明显的是,她与德勒兹和瓜塔里一起称赞塞缪尔·巴特勒是一位有先见之明的思想家,如果“他的许多主张现在与后人文主义的挑战产生共鸣”,他“肯定会感到满意”(96)。巴特勒“结合了拉马克进化论和联想主义心理学”的这一说法,在进化生物学家的历史嘲笑下得到了维护(99)。更有趣的是,巴特勒自己在当地承认,他的想法并没有“对科学价值有丝毫的自命”,而是打算“娱乐和指导无数阶层的人……享受对周围现象的推测和反思(不要太深入)”(99)。在尼尔看来,这是巴特勒强调文学至关重要的方式:“他似乎在说,如果科学要向真正的新思想敞开心扉,就必须变得更像通俗小说”(99)。这样的时刻会让任何人觉得自己像母鸡胃里的一粒玉米。前一分钟,我们还在思考生物学中最伟大的范式转变所带来的想象效果,下一分钟,我们就会冷静地思考德里达赤身裸体站在猫前的想法(90页)。显然,在这个鸟类消化的世界里,“达尔文经常被视为德勒兹和瓜塔里的先驱”(92)。在这样的世界里,我们可能会被要求相信文学对科学至关重要,这是文学学者对小说家的解释。我不想假装知道尼尔是多么认真地相信构成她的书的程序或塑造她的文学解释的公式。她似乎经常忘记了程序和公式,因为她写出了有能力的历史阐述或生动的情节总结。例如,她对雅培的自由教育理想的描述是令人愉快的(113-117)。她对威廉·莫里斯(William Morris)的精湛技艺和阿博特(Abbott)的特里斯特拉姆·尚迪(Tristram shandy)式的物质幽默(他的书完全是方形的,插图中描绘了粗糙的几何图形)有着迷人的反应。在其他时候,她似乎对自己选择的文学作品感到尴尬。在简短的结论中,在讨论了土著作家路易斯·厄德里奇和切丽·迪玛琳最近作品的重要性之后,尼尔几乎为她的选择道歉:“当然,我的维多利亚时代的文本是完全不同的。它们都是由职业的、中产阶级的英国人(只有一个例外)在帝国鼎盛时期写的”(149)。有人可能会问,这是否是厄德里奇的小说和威尔斯的小说之间最显著的区别。更重要的是,人们可能会质疑通过过去与现在的相似程度对过去的含蓄评价。虽然支持受压迫者并将历史小说与现代问题联系起来是令人钦佩的,但认为自己的道德价值观是历史的顶峰是一种非常维多利亚式的谬论(尼尔声称反对)。我希望,比起道歉,她更真诚地沉浸在想象之中。尼尔的书是否代表了19世纪描述进化的文学研究计划的最后喘息似乎值得怀疑。邓肯和格里菲斯备受瞩目的专著才刚刚面世几年,未来可能还会有更多的专著问世。然而,尼尔对月亏的描绘引起了人们的反思。她的书本质上是一本短小精悍的主题总结合集,用生动的声音写出来,充满了历史细节,但却过滤了一些软弱的公式和先入之见,使每一点信息都受到质疑。丢了这些书意味着什么?我不能说,用扭曲的碎片来传达文学史,是否比让它被遗忘更好。但我也不认为这是两种选择。尼尔的主题具有内在的趣味,她所研究的文本(至少部分文本)也是如此。
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
求助全文
约1分钟内获得全文 求助全文
来源期刊
STYLE
STYLE Multiple-
CiteScore
1.30
自引率
0.00%
发文量
21
期刊介绍: Style invites submissions that address questions of style, stylistics, and poetics, including research and theory in discourse analysis, literary and nonliterary genres, narrative, figuration, metrics, rhetorical analysis, and the pedagogy of style. Contributions may draw from such fields as literary criticism, critical theory, computational linguistics, cognitive linguistics, philosophy of language, and rhetoric and writing studies. In addition, Style publishes reviews, review-essays, surveys, interviews, translations, enumerative and annotated bibliographies, and reports on conferences.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
确定
请完成安全验证×
copy
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
右上角分享
点击右上角分享
0
联系我们:info@booksci.cn Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。 Copyright © 2023 布克学术 All rights reserved.
京ICP备2023020795号-1
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术官方微信