Reconciling Moral Responsibility with Multiplicity in Conway’s Principles

IF 0.7 3区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY
Hope Sample
{"title":"Reconciling Moral Responsibility with Multiplicity in Conway’s <i>Principles</i>","authors":"Hope Sample","doi":"10.1080/09672559.2023.2237026","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"ABSTRACTAnne Conway’s commitment to the moral responsibility of creatures, or created beings, is seemingly in tension with her unique metaphysics. Conway is committed to individual moral responsibility. Conway insists that an innocent person ought not be punished for someone else’s sin. Interesting recent work highlights a unique aspect of Conway’s position that creatures are multiplicities: not only are creatures integrated into the larger whole of creation, but also their parts are mutually integrated into one another. The latter, which I will call ‘ontological overlap,’ renders the boundaries between creatures unclear. However, creatures must be distinct enough from each other to provide a proper subject for individual moral responsibility. This contribution suggests that Conway’s account of vital power can resolve an apparent tension between ontological overlap and individual moral responsibility and, more broadly, that Conway has a relational metaphysics of moral subjecthood.KEYWORDS: Anne Conwaymoral responsiblitymultiplicitymetaphysicsparthoodpowers AcknowledgmentsThis paper greatly benefitted from the extensive feedback of two anonymous referees, Ruth Boeker, and Graham Clay. I had a helpful discussion of an earlier version of this paper at Carleton College and St. Olaf’s joint colloquium series. Finally, I would like to give a special thanks to Jason Decker, Dan Groll, Andrew Knoll, Anna Moltchanova, and Sue Sample for their feedback.Disclosure statementNo potential conflict of interest was reported by the author(s).Notes1. References to Conway’s Principles are to Conway (Citation1996), The Principles of the Most Ancient and Modern Philosophy, ed. and tr. Allison P. Coudert and Taylor Corse, hereafter cited in the text as ‘CC’, followed by page, chapter, and section number.2. For further analysis of Conway on the multiplicity of creatures, see Jasper Reid (Citation2020).3. Conway imagines an interlocutor who objects that God is responsible for sin if ‘motion and being come from the same cause, God the creator, who nevertheless remains unmoved’ (CC 58; VIII.2). She replies that although the captain is not responsible for the existence of the wind, they are appropriately praised or blamed and punished according to how they use their power to direct the ship.4. Hutton (Citation2004) provides a thorough background on Conway’s religious, personal, and philosophical context.5. See Hutton (Citation1996) for an analysis of Conway’s account of universal salvation.6. That in turn raises interesting issues concerning Conway’s modal commitments. For the purposes of this discussion, their success is at least inevitable in the sense that all creatures will succeed in the limit.7. Thanks to Anna Moltchanova for discussion of this point.8. See Jessica Gordon-Roth (Citation2018) for an interpretation of Conway that has it that she vacillates between token existence monism and type monism for the created world. Emily Thomas (Citation2020) argues that the passages that suggest vacillation can be explained away on the assumption Conway maintains priority monism, where the whole is prior to the parts. John Grey (Citation2023) analyzes the issue of Conway’s monism with attention to considerations about moral responsibility..9. One way to understand Conway’s remark that dust and sand are capable of love is that they are able to actualize that power when they transcend their current material form. To confirm that, consider that Conway attributes a creature’s ability to change species as that which enables ‘creatures to act and react upon each other in different ways’ (CC 32; VI.6). However, this is a complex issue that requires addressing her account of overall account of cognition.10. Notably, vital motion is what follows from a creature’s ‘life and will’ (CC 69; IX.9).11. Conway’s use of the term ‘instrument’ suggests that either God is the only cause, i.e., occasionalism, or all creaturely agency that generates motion is shared agency, a product of divine and creaturely coordination, i.e., concurrentism. An occasionalist interpretation of Conway’s account of causation could be developed that also preserves her commitment to creaturely moral responsibility, and I do not aim to rule out that interpretation in this discussion. Nevertheless, as a simplifying assumption, to avoid generating more puzzles about moral responsibility, I will assume that creatures make a partial causal contribution to their actions. See Alfred Freddoso (1991) for an account of occasionalism and concurrentism.12. See Thomas (Citation2017) for an account of Conway’s temporal holenmerism, a discussion that also provides a way to make sense of divine immanence alongside transcendence.13. See Jacqueline Broad (Citation2018) for insight into the temporal aspects of emanation causation, and see Christia Mercer (Citation2012) for a contextualization of Conway’s account of causation within a history of early modern Platonism.","PeriodicalId":51828,"journal":{"name":"INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHICAL STUDIES","volume":"14 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.7000,"publicationDate":"2023-03-15","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":"0","resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHICAL STUDIES","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.1080/09672559.2023.2237026","RegionNum":3,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"0","JCRName":"PHILOSOPHY","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0

Abstract

ABSTRACTAnne Conway’s commitment to the moral responsibility of creatures, or created beings, is seemingly in tension with her unique metaphysics. Conway is committed to individual moral responsibility. Conway insists that an innocent person ought not be punished for someone else’s sin. Interesting recent work highlights a unique aspect of Conway’s position that creatures are multiplicities: not only are creatures integrated into the larger whole of creation, but also their parts are mutually integrated into one another. The latter, which I will call ‘ontological overlap,’ renders the boundaries between creatures unclear. However, creatures must be distinct enough from each other to provide a proper subject for individual moral responsibility. This contribution suggests that Conway’s account of vital power can resolve an apparent tension between ontological overlap and individual moral responsibility and, more broadly, that Conway has a relational metaphysics of moral subjecthood.KEYWORDS: Anne Conwaymoral responsiblitymultiplicitymetaphysicsparthoodpowers AcknowledgmentsThis paper greatly benefitted from the extensive feedback of two anonymous referees, Ruth Boeker, and Graham Clay. I had a helpful discussion of an earlier version of this paper at Carleton College and St. Olaf’s joint colloquium series. Finally, I would like to give a special thanks to Jason Decker, Dan Groll, Andrew Knoll, Anna Moltchanova, and Sue Sample for their feedback.Disclosure statementNo potential conflict of interest was reported by the author(s).Notes1. References to Conway’s Principles are to Conway (Citation1996), The Principles of the Most Ancient and Modern Philosophy, ed. and tr. Allison P. Coudert and Taylor Corse, hereafter cited in the text as ‘CC’, followed by page, chapter, and section number.2. For further analysis of Conway on the multiplicity of creatures, see Jasper Reid (Citation2020).3. Conway imagines an interlocutor who objects that God is responsible for sin if ‘motion and being come from the same cause, God the creator, who nevertheless remains unmoved’ (CC 58; VIII.2). She replies that although the captain is not responsible for the existence of the wind, they are appropriately praised or blamed and punished according to how they use their power to direct the ship.4. Hutton (Citation2004) provides a thorough background on Conway’s religious, personal, and philosophical context.5. See Hutton (Citation1996) for an analysis of Conway’s account of universal salvation.6. That in turn raises interesting issues concerning Conway’s modal commitments. For the purposes of this discussion, their success is at least inevitable in the sense that all creatures will succeed in the limit.7. Thanks to Anna Moltchanova for discussion of this point.8. See Jessica Gordon-Roth (Citation2018) for an interpretation of Conway that has it that she vacillates between token existence monism and type monism for the created world. Emily Thomas (Citation2020) argues that the passages that suggest vacillation can be explained away on the assumption Conway maintains priority monism, where the whole is prior to the parts. John Grey (Citation2023) analyzes the issue of Conway’s monism with attention to considerations about moral responsibility..9. One way to understand Conway’s remark that dust and sand are capable of love is that they are able to actualize that power when they transcend their current material form. To confirm that, consider that Conway attributes a creature’s ability to change species as that which enables ‘creatures to act and react upon each other in different ways’ (CC 32; VI.6). However, this is a complex issue that requires addressing her account of overall account of cognition.10. Notably, vital motion is what follows from a creature’s ‘life and will’ (CC 69; IX.9).11. Conway’s use of the term ‘instrument’ suggests that either God is the only cause, i.e., occasionalism, or all creaturely agency that generates motion is shared agency, a product of divine and creaturely coordination, i.e., concurrentism. An occasionalist interpretation of Conway’s account of causation could be developed that also preserves her commitment to creaturely moral responsibility, and I do not aim to rule out that interpretation in this discussion. Nevertheless, as a simplifying assumption, to avoid generating more puzzles about moral responsibility, I will assume that creatures make a partial causal contribution to their actions. See Alfred Freddoso (1991) for an account of occasionalism and concurrentism.12. See Thomas (Citation2017) for an account of Conway’s temporal holenmerism, a discussion that also provides a way to make sense of divine immanence alongside transcendence.13. See Jacqueline Broad (Citation2018) for insight into the temporal aspects of emanation causation, and see Christia Mercer (Citation2012) for a contextualization of Conway’s account of causation within a history of early modern Platonism.
康威原则中道德责任与多重性的调和
【摘要】安妮·康威对受造物的道德责任的承诺,似乎与她独特的形而上学相矛盾。康威致力于个人道德责任。康威坚持认为,一个无辜的人不应该因为别人的罪而受到惩罚。最近有趣的研究突出了康威观点的一个独特方面,即生物是多样性的:生物不仅被整合到更大的创造整体中,而且它们的各个部分也相互整合。后者,我称之为“本体论上的重叠”,使生物之间的界限变得不清晰。然而,生物彼此之间必须有足够的区别,以提供个人道德责任的适当主体。这一贡献表明,康威对生命力的描述可以解决本体论重叠和个人道德责任之间明显的紧张关系,更广泛地说,康威有一种道德主体性的关系形而上学。关键字:安妮·康威道德责任多元形而上学独立力量致谢本文极大地受益于两位匿名审稿人Ruth Boeker和Graham Clay的广泛反馈。我在卡尔顿学院和圣奥拉夫的联合系列研讨会上对这篇论文的早期版本进行了有益的讨论。最后,我要特别感谢Jason Decker、Dan Groll、Andrew Knoll、Anna Moltchanova和Sue Sample的反馈。披露声明作者未报告潜在的利益冲突。引用康威原理的地方是康威(Citation1996),《最古老和最现代哲学的原理》,艾莉森·p·库德特和泰勒·科斯编译,下文以“CC”形式引用,后面跟着页、章和节号2。关于康威对生物多样性的进一步分析,见Jasper Reid (Citation2020)。康威想象了一个对话者,他反对上帝对罪负责,如果“运动和存在来自同一个原因,上帝是创造者,但他仍然不动”(CC 58;VIII.2)。她回答说,虽然船长对风的存在不负有责任,但根据他们如何使用他们的力量来指挥船只,他们应该受到适当的赞扬或指责和惩罚。赫顿(Citation2004)对康威的宗教、个人和哲学背景进行了全面的介绍。参见Hutton (Citation1996)对康威关于普遍救赎的解释的分析。这反过来又提出了关于康威模态承诺的有趣问题。就本讨论的目的而言,它们的成功至少在某种意义上是不可避免的,因为所有生物都将在有限的范围内取得成功。感谢Anna Moltchanova对这一点的讨论。参见Jessica Gordon-Roth (Citation2018)对康威的解读,她在被创造世界的象征性存在一元论和类型一元论之间摇摆不定。艾米丽·托马斯(Citation2020)认为,暗示摇摆不定的段落可以用康威坚持优先一元论的假设来解释,即整体优先于部分。约翰·格雷(引用2023)分析了康威一元论的问题,关注道德责任的考虑……理解康威所说的尘埃和沙子有爱的能力的一种方式是,当它们超越目前的物质形态时,它们能够实现这种力量。为了证实这一点,考虑到康威将生物改变物种的能力归结为使“生物以不同的方式相互作用和反应”(CC 32;VI.6)。然而,这是一个复杂的问题,需要解决她对认知的总体描述。值得注意的是,生命运动是从一个生物的“生命和意志”中产生的(cc69;IX.9)。。康威对“工具”一词的使用表明,要么上帝是唯一的原因,即偶然性,要么所有产生运动的生物机构都是共享的机构,是神圣和生物协调的产物,即并发性。我们可以对康威的因果关系提出一种偶然性的解释,这种解释也保留了她对生物道德责任的承诺,我并不打算在这次讨论中排除这种解释。然而,作为一个简化的假设,为了避免产生更多关于道德责任的困惑,我将假设生物对它们的行为有部分因果贡献。参见Alfred Freddoso(1991)关于偶然性和同时性的解释。参见托马斯(引文2017)对康威的时间全息论的解释,这一讨论也提供了一种理解神的内在性和超越性的方法。参见杰奎琳·布罗德(Citation2018)深入了解辐射因果关系的时间方面,参见克里斯蒂亚·默瑟(Citation2012)了解康威在早期现代柏拉图主义历史中对因果关系的描述。
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
求助全文
约1分钟内获得全文 求助全文
来源期刊
CiteScore
0.90
自引率
0.00%
发文量
29
期刊介绍: The International Journal of Philosophical Studies (IJPS) publishes academic articles of the highest quality from both analytic and continental traditions and provides a forum for publishing on a broader range of issues than is currently available in philosophical journals. IJPS also publishes annual special issues devoted to key thematic areas or to critical engagements with contemporary philosophers of note. Through its Discussion section, it provides a lively forum for exchange of ideas and encourages dialogue and mutual comprehension across all philosophical traditions. The journal also contains an extensive book review section, including occasional book symposia. It also provides Critical Notices which review major books or themes in depth.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
确定
请完成安全验证×
copy
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
右上角分享
点击右上角分享
0
联系我们:info@booksci.cn Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。 Copyright © 2023 布克学术 All rights reserved.
京ICP备2023020795号-1
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术官方微信