Vagueness and the Evolution of Consciousness

IF 2.8 1区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY
Angela Mendelovici, David Bourget
{"title":"<i>Vagueness and the Evolution of Consciousness</i>","authors":"Angela Mendelovici, David Bourget","doi":"10.1215/00318108-10317619","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"Michael Tye is perhaps best known for his defense of tracking representationalism, a view that combines representationalism (the view that an experience’s phenomenal character is determined by its representational content) with a tracking theory of representation (the view that mental representation is a matter of causal covariation, carrying information, or, more generally, tracking). In Vagueness and the Evolution of Consciousness, Tye takes an unexpected turn, endorsing a combination of tracking representationalism and panpsychism, which is understood here as the view that phenomenal consciousness is a primitive feature of the fundamental constituents of reality. While Tye takes both panpsychism and tracking representationalism to fail as theories of consciousness, he argues that their combination—-panpsychist representationalism—-can avoid the problems of both.Chapter 1 of Tye’s book frames the discussion in terms of the problem of vagueness for materialist theories of consciousness (theories that identify or ground consciousness in physical or functional properties). The problem is that the properties that materialist theories identify consciousness with (or ground consciousness in) are vague in that they admit borderline cases.1 For example, functional properties are vague since there are borderline cases in which it is indeterminate whether something plays the relevant role. Since materialism identifies consciousness with (or grounds it in) vague properties, it is committed to the vagueness of consciousness. The problem is that it is not vague whether something is conscious. In brief, assuming consciousness exists, it seems we are forced to reject one of these two claims, both of which are highly plausible according to Tye: (1) Materialism is true of consciousness.(2) Consciousness is sharp (i.e., not vague).Chapter 2 considers a possible resolution of the problem that rejects neither materialism nor the sharpness of consciousness: Russellian monist panpsychism (or panpsychism for short), the view that consciousness is the intrinsic, categorical nature of the physical. This broadly materialist view appears to avoid vagueness by taking all fundamental entities to be determinately conscious.Tye rejects panpsychism, citing several well-known problems. The main problems center around panpsychism’s alleged inability to offer an intelligible explanation of nonfundamental conscious experiences (such as, presumably, our conscious experiences), where an intelligible explanation of A in terms of B is one in which B a priori entails A. It seems that the facts about fundamental instances of consciousness, even in combination with the causal dispositional facts that define our internal organization and relationships to the environment, do not a priori entail that there are nonfundamental experiences like ours.Tye also claims that, aside from panpsychism’s internal difficulties, the view does not actually help with the problem of vagueness: the panpsychist identifies nonfundamental experiences with fundamental experiences organized in particular ways, but the relevant organizational properties are vague, so the theory predicts borderline cases of consciousness (29). So, it is not in fact compatible with the sharpness of consciousness.Chapter 3 switches gears to provide a defense of representationalism and the argument from transparency, overviewing well-worn discussions. Tye defends a version of representationalism, property representationalism, on which the phenomenal character of an experience is determined by the properties it represents. He combines this representationalism with a tracking theory of mental representation, on which representation is a matter of causally indicating, having the function of indicating, or otherwise tracking something. For example, on Tye’s tracking representationalism, an experience with a reddish phenomenal character is an experience that tracks redness. While Tye defends tracking representationalism, he is aware that the view faces a vagueness problem: since it is vague whether an internal state tracks something, the view is incompatible with the sharpness of consciousness.Chapter 4 presents Tye’s positive proposal, which is a combination of panpsychism and representationalism. According to this panpsychist representationalism, fundamental entities have consciousness*, which is mere consciousness (consciousness without any particular phenomenal character). There is something it is like to be a fundamental entity, though there is nothing in particular that it is like to be it.When fundamental entities “are arranged so as to form states that play the sort of role assigned to conscious states in GWT [global workspace theory]” (88), they form nonfundamental entities that are conscious*. Thus, like traditional panpsychism, representationalist panpsychism is committed to fundamental consciousness-related features combining to form nonfundamental consciousness-related features.Consciousness* is distinct from consciousness, which Tye (at this point in the book) takes to be the having of particular phenomenal characters. When conscious* states play the roles specified by GWT, which include that of tracking worldly properties, they thereby have the tracked properties as part of their phenomenal characters. For example, a conscious state with a reddish phenomenal character is a conscious* state that plays the roles specified by GWT and tracks the property of redness.Tye claims that this view solves the problem of vagueness: it is a materialist view that is compatible with the sharpness of consciousness*. The view, though, is incompatible with the sharpness of consciousness, since consciousness requires tracking and tracking is vague. Tye explains away our intuition that consciousness is sharp by claiming that the sharpness of consciousness* misleads us into thinking that consciousness is sharp (79).The book concludes with a chapter on the neurobiology of consciousness, reviewing some empirical hypotheses regarding the location of consciousness in the brain and applying panpsychist representationalism to determine which life forms are conscious.While Tye’s version of panpsychism differs from traditional versions, intelligibility problems remain. For one, Tye fails to intelligibly explain how the consciousness* of fundamental entities “transfers” (88) to nonfundamental entities. He takes this to be a matter of how fundamental entities are arranged so as to play the roles of GWT, but it is unclear how any kind of functional arrangement of conscious* fundamental entities can account for nonfundamental consciousness*. This is a straightforward instance of panpsychism’s combination problem.Tye also fails to intelligibly explain the having of particular phenomenal characters. He takes conscious states with specific phenomenal characters to be nonfundamental conscious* states that track worldly properties, but there is no intelligible explanation of why a nonfundamental conscious* state’s tracking a particular worldly property should result in a conscious state with a particular phenomenal character.2Tye’s solution to the problem of vagueness involves claiming that (1) consciousness* is sharp even though (2) consciousness is vague and that (3) the appearance of a dilemma arises because we mistakenly attribute the sharpness of consciousness* to our consciousness. There are problems with all three claims.Regarding (1), one might worry that although Tye’s view allows that the consciousness* of fundamental entities is sharp, it does not allow the consciousness* of nonfundamental entities to be sharp. This is because it takes nonfundamental entities to be conscious* when conscious* fundamental entities “are arranged so as to form states that play the sort of role assigned to conscious states in GWT” (88) but the property of being thus arranged is vague.3Claim (2) also seems questionable. Tye argues that there can be borderline cases of having a particular phenomenal character, such as a borderline case of pain (13–14). We agree that the term “pain” is vague and that, if we accept that corresponding to vague terms there are vague properties, the property of having a pain is vague, too. However, it seems clear that whatever we call the above-mentioned indeterminate pain state, it has a sharp phenomenal property, Q: there is a specific, fully determinate way that it feels. Indeed, Q is plausibly more fundamental than any vague phenomenal properties the state has in that the state instantiates any such vague phenomenal properties in virtue of having Q. Even if it is right to say that there are vague phenomenal properties, there are also sharp phenomenal properties, and Tye’s view cannot accommodate them.Claim (3) states that the appearance of a dilemma arises because we mistakenly attribute the sharpness of consciousness* to our consciousness. But if the objection to (1) is correct, then on Tye’s view, our own consciousness* is not sharp. So, we do not have any observable sharp consciousness-like properties with which to conflate our allegedly vague consciousness (and surely we are not conflating the sharp consciousness* of quarks with our own consciousness!). The objection to (2) also makes (3) implausible because it offers a principled reason for thinking that some macroscopic conscious properties are sharp. As far as consciousness as we know it is concerned, the dilemma is unresolved.To generate a dilemma, materialism must be committed to consciousness being vague. But, one might suggest, materialism is not thus committed. While many existing materialist theories invoke vague physical or functional properties, these theories can be precisified to instead invoke sharp physical or functional properties. For example, instead of identifying consciousness with neural oscillations with a frequency of roughly 40 hertz (Crick and Koch’s “astonishing hypothesis”), the materialist could identify consciousness with neural oscillations at exactly 39.12409825–40.185282624 hertz (call this the sharpened astonishing hypothesis; of course, the term “neural” also needs a similar precisification. If such views are available, then there is not even a prima facie incompatibility between materialism and the sharpness of consciousness.Tye briefly considers something like this precisification strategy on behalf of the nonreductive materialist, who takes consciousness to be grounded in (but not identical to) physical or functional features. Tye rejects the resulting view, citing explanatory challenges. The interesting problem for our purposes is that such views cannot explain why one physical/functional state grounds consciousness while another nearby one does not (10–11).4We certainly agree that precisified materialist theories face a challenge in explaining consciousness. But this does not affect the point that the availability of such precisifications means that materialism is not in fact committed to the vagueness of consciousness. Instead, materialism is, at best, committed to accepting that consciousness and its constituting physical/functional features are either both sharp or both vague.Assuming, along with Tye (at the beginning of the book), that consciousness is sharp, the materialist is forced to take consciousness to be a matter of sharp physical or functional properties. This is where the problems for materialism really get started. As we have seen, such a view faces an explanatory worry: why should one physical/functional state give rise to consciousness but not another? This worry is related to well-known explanatory-gap style worries in that if the explanatory gap could be bridged, these worries would dissolve: if there was an intelligible explanation for why a precise physical/functional feature gives rise to consciousness and no such explanation for nearby physical/functional features, there would be no further question of the sort raised by Tye.However, we think Tye is onto something in claiming that precisified versions of materialism face special challenges. Precisified theories face an additional “structural mismatch” worry: they imply that some tiny physical differences make large phenomenal differences (i.e., that some apparently large differences are small or vice versa). Of course, a posteriori physicalists have a response at hand: there is only one difference, and any impression to the contrary is an illusion. It seems to us, however, that the need to posit cognitive illusions to explain away such an apparent structural mismatch is a significant cost above and beyond what posteriori physicalists already accept.In short, the materialist has an obvious way to dissolve Tye’s dilemma: the precisification strategy. But this strategy does not come without problems, which would be interesting to explore.We recommend Tye’s Vagueness and the Evolution of Consciousness to anyone interested in representationalism, panpsychism, or challenges to materialism arising from vagueness. While we are not convinced that the book succeeds in solving the problems it sets out to solve or that it correctly construes materialism’s troubles in this area, it raises important questions and makes headway in charting the prospects of combining panpsychism with views about the relationship between consciousness and intentionality, which is an interesting and, we think, promising area for future research.","PeriodicalId":48129,"journal":{"name":"PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW","volume":"43 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":2.8000,"publicationDate":"2023-04-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":"0","resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.1215/00318108-10317619","RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"0","JCRName":"PHILOSOPHY","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0

Abstract

Michael Tye is perhaps best known for his defense of tracking representationalism, a view that combines representationalism (the view that an experience’s phenomenal character is determined by its representational content) with a tracking theory of representation (the view that mental representation is a matter of causal covariation, carrying information, or, more generally, tracking). In Vagueness and the Evolution of Consciousness, Tye takes an unexpected turn, endorsing a combination of tracking representationalism and panpsychism, which is understood here as the view that phenomenal consciousness is a primitive feature of the fundamental constituents of reality. While Tye takes both panpsychism and tracking representationalism to fail as theories of consciousness, he argues that their combination—-panpsychist representationalism—-can avoid the problems of both.Chapter 1 of Tye’s book frames the discussion in terms of the problem of vagueness for materialist theories of consciousness (theories that identify or ground consciousness in physical or functional properties). The problem is that the properties that materialist theories identify consciousness with (or ground consciousness in) are vague in that they admit borderline cases.1 For example, functional properties are vague since there are borderline cases in which it is indeterminate whether something plays the relevant role. Since materialism identifies consciousness with (or grounds it in) vague properties, it is committed to the vagueness of consciousness. The problem is that it is not vague whether something is conscious. In brief, assuming consciousness exists, it seems we are forced to reject one of these two claims, both of which are highly plausible according to Tye: (1) Materialism is true of consciousness.(2) Consciousness is sharp (i.e., not vague).Chapter 2 considers a possible resolution of the problem that rejects neither materialism nor the sharpness of consciousness: Russellian monist panpsychism (or panpsychism for short), the view that consciousness is the intrinsic, categorical nature of the physical. This broadly materialist view appears to avoid vagueness by taking all fundamental entities to be determinately conscious.Tye rejects panpsychism, citing several well-known problems. The main problems center around panpsychism’s alleged inability to offer an intelligible explanation of nonfundamental conscious experiences (such as, presumably, our conscious experiences), where an intelligible explanation of A in terms of B is one in which B a priori entails A. It seems that the facts about fundamental instances of consciousness, even in combination with the causal dispositional facts that define our internal organization and relationships to the environment, do not a priori entail that there are nonfundamental experiences like ours.Tye also claims that, aside from panpsychism’s internal difficulties, the view does not actually help with the problem of vagueness: the panpsychist identifies nonfundamental experiences with fundamental experiences organized in particular ways, but the relevant organizational properties are vague, so the theory predicts borderline cases of consciousness (29). So, it is not in fact compatible with the sharpness of consciousness.Chapter 3 switches gears to provide a defense of representationalism and the argument from transparency, overviewing well-worn discussions. Tye defends a version of representationalism, property representationalism, on which the phenomenal character of an experience is determined by the properties it represents. He combines this representationalism with a tracking theory of mental representation, on which representation is a matter of causally indicating, having the function of indicating, or otherwise tracking something. For example, on Tye’s tracking representationalism, an experience with a reddish phenomenal character is an experience that tracks redness. While Tye defends tracking representationalism, he is aware that the view faces a vagueness problem: since it is vague whether an internal state tracks something, the view is incompatible with the sharpness of consciousness.Chapter 4 presents Tye’s positive proposal, which is a combination of panpsychism and representationalism. According to this panpsychist representationalism, fundamental entities have consciousness*, which is mere consciousness (consciousness without any particular phenomenal character). There is something it is like to be a fundamental entity, though there is nothing in particular that it is like to be it.When fundamental entities “are arranged so as to form states that play the sort of role assigned to conscious states in GWT [global workspace theory]” (88), they form nonfundamental entities that are conscious*. Thus, like traditional panpsychism, representationalist panpsychism is committed to fundamental consciousness-related features combining to form nonfundamental consciousness-related features.Consciousness* is distinct from consciousness, which Tye (at this point in the book) takes to be the having of particular phenomenal characters. When conscious* states play the roles specified by GWT, which include that of tracking worldly properties, they thereby have the tracked properties as part of their phenomenal characters. For example, a conscious state with a reddish phenomenal character is a conscious* state that plays the roles specified by GWT and tracks the property of redness.Tye claims that this view solves the problem of vagueness: it is a materialist view that is compatible with the sharpness of consciousness*. The view, though, is incompatible with the sharpness of consciousness, since consciousness requires tracking and tracking is vague. Tye explains away our intuition that consciousness is sharp by claiming that the sharpness of consciousness* misleads us into thinking that consciousness is sharp (79).The book concludes with a chapter on the neurobiology of consciousness, reviewing some empirical hypotheses regarding the location of consciousness in the brain and applying panpsychist representationalism to determine which life forms are conscious.While Tye’s version of panpsychism differs from traditional versions, intelligibility problems remain. For one, Tye fails to intelligibly explain how the consciousness* of fundamental entities “transfers” (88) to nonfundamental entities. He takes this to be a matter of how fundamental entities are arranged so as to play the roles of GWT, but it is unclear how any kind of functional arrangement of conscious* fundamental entities can account for nonfundamental consciousness*. This is a straightforward instance of panpsychism’s combination problem.Tye also fails to intelligibly explain the having of particular phenomenal characters. He takes conscious states with specific phenomenal characters to be nonfundamental conscious* states that track worldly properties, but there is no intelligible explanation of why a nonfundamental conscious* state’s tracking a particular worldly property should result in a conscious state with a particular phenomenal character.2Tye’s solution to the problem of vagueness involves claiming that (1) consciousness* is sharp even though (2) consciousness is vague and that (3) the appearance of a dilemma arises because we mistakenly attribute the sharpness of consciousness* to our consciousness. There are problems with all three claims.Regarding (1), one might worry that although Tye’s view allows that the consciousness* of fundamental entities is sharp, it does not allow the consciousness* of nonfundamental entities to be sharp. This is because it takes nonfundamental entities to be conscious* when conscious* fundamental entities “are arranged so as to form states that play the sort of role assigned to conscious states in GWT” (88) but the property of being thus arranged is vague.3Claim (2) also seems questionable. Tye argues that there can be borderline cases of having a particular phenomenal character, such as a borderline case of pain (13–14). We agree that the term “pain” is vague and that, if we accept that corresponding to vague terms there are vague properties, the property of having a pain is vague, too. However, it seems clear that whatever we call the above-mentioned indeterminate pain state, it has a sharp phenomenal property, Q: there is a specific, fully determinate way that it feels. Indeed, Q is plausibly more fundamental than any vague phenomenal properties the state has in that the state instantiates any such vague phenomenal properties in virtue of having Q. Even if it is right to say that there are vague phenomenal properties, there are also sharp phenomenal properties, and Tye’s view cannot accommodate them.Claim (3) states that the appearance of a dilemma arises because we mistakenly attribute the sharpness of consciousness* to our consciousness. But if the objection to (1) is correct, then on Tye’s view, our own consciousness* is not sharp. So, we do not have any observable sharp consciousness-like properties with which to conflate our allegedly vague consciousness (and surely we are not conflating the sharp consciousness* of quarks with our own consciousness!). The objection to (2) also makes (3) implausible because it offers a principled reason for thinking that some macroscopic conscious properties are sharp. As far as consciousness as we know it is concerned, the dilemma is unresolved.To generate a dilemma, materialism must be committed to consciousness being vague. But, one might suggest, materialism is not thus committed. While many existing materialist theories invoke vague physical or functional properties, these theories can be precisified to instead invoke sharp physical or functional properties. For example, instead of identifying consciousness with neural oscillations with a frequency of roughly 40 hertz (Crick and Koch’s “astonishing hypothesis”), the materialist could identify consciousness with neural oscillations at exactly 39.12409825–40.185282624 hertz (call this the sharpened astonishing hypothesis; of course, the term “neural” also needs a similar precisification. If such views are available, then there is not even a prima facie incompatibility between materialism and the sharpness of consciousness.Tye briefly considers something like this precisification strategy on behalf of the nonreductive materialist, who takes consciousness to be grounded in (but not identical to) physical or functional features. Tye rejects the resulting view, citing explanatory challenges. The interesting problem for our purposes is that such views cannot explain why one physical/functional state grounds consciousness while another nearby one does not (10–11).4We certainly agree that precisified materialist theories face a challenge in explaining consciousness. But this does not affect the point that the availability of such precisifications means that materialism is not in fact committed to the vagueness of consciousness. Instead, materialism is, at best, committed to accepting that consciousness and its constituting physical/functional features are either both sharp or both vague.Assuming, along with Tye (at the beginning of the book), that consciousness is sharp, the materialist is forced to take consciousness to be a matter of sharp physical or functional properties. This is where the problems for materialism really get started. As we have seen, such a view faces an explanatory worry: why should one physical/functional state give rise to consciousness but not another? This worry is related to well-known explanatory-gap style worries in that if the explanatory gap could be bridged, these worries would dissolve: if there was an intelligible explanation for why a precise physical/functional feature gives rise to consciousness and no such explanation for nearby physical/functional features, there would be no further question of the sort raised by Tye.However, we think Tye is onto something in claiming that precisified versions of materialism face special challenges. Precisified theories face an additional “structural mismatch” worry: they imply that some tiny physical differences make large phenomenal differences (i.e., that some apparently large differences are small or vice versa). Of course, a posteriori physicalists have a response at hand: there is only one difference, and any impression to the contrary is an illusion. It seems to us, however, that the need to posit cognitive illusions to explain away such an apparent structural mismatch is a significant cost above and beyond what posteriori physicalists already accept.In short, the materialist has an obvious way to dissolve Tye’s dilemma: the precisification strategy. But this strategy does not come without problems, which would be interesting to explore.We recommend Tye’s Vagueness and the Evolution of Consciousness to anyone interested in representationalism, panpsychism, or challenges to materialism arising from vagueness. While we are not convinced that the book succeeds in solving the problems it sets out to solve or that it correctly construes materialism’s troubles in this area, it raises important questions and makes headway in charting the prospects of combining panpsychism with views about the relationship between consciousness and intentionality, which is an interesting and, we think, promising area for future research.
模糊与意识的进化
意识*不同于意识,泰伊(在书的这一点上)认为意识是具有特定的现象性特征。当有意识的状态扮演GWT指定的角色时,其中包括追踪世俗属性,因此它们将被追踪的属性作为其现象性特征的一部分。例如,带有红色现象特征的意识状态是一种意识*状态,它扮演GWT指定的角色并跟踪红色的属性。泰认为这种观点解决了模糊性的问题:它是一种唯物主义的观点,与意识的尖锐性是相容的*。然而,这种观点与意识的清晰度是不相容的,因为意识需要跟踪,而跟踪是模糊的。泰解释了我们认为意识是敏锐的直觉,他声称意识的敏锐会误导我们认为意识是敏锐的(79)。这本书的最后一章是关于意识的神经生物学,回顾了一些关于意识在大脑中的位置的经验假设,并应用泛心论表征主义来确定哪些生命形式是有意识的。虽然泰的泛心论版本不同于传统版本,但可理解性问题仍然存在。首先,泰没能清楚地解释基本实体的意识*是如何“转移”到非基本实体的。他认为这是一个基本实体如何安排以扮演GWT角色的问题,但不清楚有意识的基本实体的任何一种功能安排如何解释非基本意识。这是泛心论的组合问题的一个直接例子。泰也没能清楚地解释特殊现象人物的出现。他认为具有特定现象特征的意识状态是追踪世俗属性的非基本意识状态,但是对于为什么一个追踪特定世俗属性的非基本意识状态会导致具有特定现象特征的意识状态,并没有可理解的解释。tye对模糊性问题的解决方案包括宣称(1)意识*是敏锐的,尽管(2)意识是模糊的;(3)出现困境的原因是我们错误地将意识*的敏锐归因于我们的意识。这三种说法都有问题。关于(1),人们可能会担心,尽管泰的观点允许基本实体的意识*是尖锐的,但它不允许非基本实体的意识*是尖锐的。这是因为当有意识的基本实体“被安排以形成在GWT中赋予意识状态的角色”(88)时,非基本实体是有意识的,但这种安排的性质是模糊的。索赔(2)似乎也有问题。Tye认为,可能存在具有特定现象性特征的边缘案例,例如疼痛的边缘案例(13-14)。我们同意"疼痛"这个术语是模糊的,如果我们接受与模糊术语相对应的是模糊的属性,那么疼痛的属性也是模糊的。然而,似乎很清楚,无论我们称之为上述不确定的疼痛状态,它都有一个尖锐的现象属性,Q:它有一种特定的、完全确定的感觉方式。事实上,Q似乎比状态所具有的任何模糊的现象性质都更基本因为状态通过Q实例化了任何这种模糊的现象性质即使说存在模糊的现象性质是正确的,也存在尖锐的现象性质,而Tye的观点无法容纳它们。命题(3)指出,困境的出现是因为我们错误地将意识*的敏锐性归因于我们的意识。但是,如果对(1)的反对意见是正确的,那么,依泰的观点,我们自己的意识*是不敏锐的。因此,我们没有任何可观察到的类似于敏锐意识的特性来将我们所谓的模糊意识混为一谈(当然,我们也不会将夸克的敏锐意识*与我们自己的意识混为一谈!)对(2)的反对也使得(3)难以置信,因为它提供了一个原则性的理由来思考一些宏观的意识属性是尖锐的。就我们所知的意识而言,这个困境还没有解决。唯物主义要产生一种困境,就必须致力于意识的模糊性。但是,有人可能会说,唯物主义并非如此。虽然许多现有的唯物主义理论援引了模糊的物理或功能特性,但这些理论可以精确地援引明确的物理或功能特性。
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
求助全文
约1分钟内获得全文 求助全文
来源期刊
PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW
PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW PHILOSOPHY-
CiteScore
7.40
自引率
0.00%
发文量
17
期刊介绍: In continuous publication since 1892, the Philosophical Review has a long-standing reputation for excellence and has published many papers now considered classics in the field, such as W. V. O. Quine"s “Two Dogmas of Empiricism,” Thomas Nagel"s “What Is It Like to Be a Bat?” and the early work of John Rawls. The journal aims to publish original scholarly work in all areas of analytic philosophy, with an emphasis on material of general interest to academic philosophers, and is one of the few journals in the discipline to publish book reviews.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
确定
请完成安全验证×
copy
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
右上角分享
点击右上角分享
0
联系我们:info@booksci.cn Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。 Copyright © 2023 布克学术 All rights reserved.
京ICP备2023020795号-1
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术官方微信