The Moral Habitat

IF 2.8 1区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY
Helga Varden
{"title":"<i>The Moral Habitat</i>","authors":"Helga Varden","doi":"10.1215/00318108-10294487","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"Those who love philosophy books that present new, exciting, and complex theories have been given a gift in Barbara Herman’s The Moral Habitat. In my view, it is also a gift to Kant, since it develops a deeply Kantian account of deliberation as part of showing how perfect and imperfect duties can be seen as working together in a dynamic moral (eco)system of duties of right and of virtue. In the process of doing this, Herman develops a new, intriguing account of imperfect duties and replaces many of Kant’s bad examples with good ones, providing an ideal model for how to argue by example, whether one is Kantian or not. Moreover, by her many intriguing and rich examples, Herman makes many of Kant’s ideas, as well as her revisionary Kantian ideas, available as resources in our shared philosophical practice. Of course, Kantians and others will disagree with some of her arguments and proposals, but many of these discussions yet to come will themselves become important additions to the existing scholarship. Fortunately, too, for a book that presents a new and complex Kantian theory, it does not get bogged down in specific scholarly disputes on particular topics; instead, it stays focused on developing and communicating the big moves, the big picture. Finally, as with all Herman’s brilliant writings, The Moral Habitat is beautifully written—with care, wit, and wisdom. It is, in other words, among the best of gifts: a reliable friend to think with about some very complex and difficult topics—philosophical and human—from now on.The moral habitat is defined as “a made environment, created by and for free and equal persons living together,” and Herman consequently puts “the deliberating and morally active person at the center of a generative moral enterprise” (ix). Herman’s book is furthermore divided into three parts: part 1 “Three Imperfect Duties,” part 2 “Kantian Resources,” and part 3 “Living in the Moral Habitat.” Part 1 serves to rid readers of some ingrained expectations they are likely to have of Kantian discussions of imperfect duty, such as the expectation that this will mostly be a discussion of beneficence or that it will assume a specific, historically prominent interpretation of motive or incentive. In these ways, Herman helps us to open our philosophical minds and stimulates our philosophical curiosity and imagination. More specifically, after the first chapter, focused on “Framing the Question (What We Can Learn From Imperfect Duties),” Herman provides chapter-length discussions of gratitude, giving, and due care (chaps. 2, 3, and 4, resp.). Her main strategy throughout these chapters is to develop each idea from the bottom up, working from many rich and intriguing examples to a summary section in each chapter—called “middle work”—where she draws our (philosophically trained minds’) attention to her main findings. For example, the main focus of chapter 3 is the puzzle of why giving too much—such as paying too much when repaying a loan or giving too much as a gift—causes damage. In the “middle work” section following these examples, Herman then draws out some metanormative claims about how permissibility and wrongness relate to one another, with a special focus on her claim throughout this chapter that there is a “possible consistency of not impermissible and morally wrong” (43).Herman’s strategy in this first part is effective and productive. It shows us that figuring out what to do in any situation (good deliberation) requires us to pay attention to its complexity—an interpretation of Kant’s statement that wisdom requires “judgement sharpened by experience” (Kant 1996)—and to how many rights, duties, and obligations interweave in specific situations. The examples also help everyone to be ready for the more philosophically sophisticated discussions in the “middle work” sections and, of course, for the rest of the book. Herman’s strategy here also helps rid us of the bad habit of looking for simple solutions to complex questions—whether our preferred simplifying method is to focus on one, allegedly core, example (of Kant’s) or one principle, or one interpretation thereof (such as the so-called categorical imperative procedure). Living life well, on our own and together with others, is much more difficult than this at any given moment and through time (as the circumstances of our lives evolve and change). In these ways—and throughout the book—Herman shows us how to deliberate within the Kantian framework; Aristotle is no longer the only (classical) alternative in town on the topic of good deliberation.Part 2 zooms in on Kantian practical philosophical resources, especially as they are found in, and can be further developed from, the Groundwork for the Metaphysics of Morals and The Metaphysics of Morals. Herman’s overall aim here is to “introduce and argue for a revisionary interpretation of Kant’s ethics (broadly construed)… [as] guided by two lodestars: that the resulting reading be convincingly Kant’s ethics, in both letter and spirit, and that the revision justify itself by giving us a better theory, in its own terms and in ours” (73). More specifically, chapter 6 (“The Kantian System of Duties”) presents Herman’s interpretation of many basic interpretive and philosophical ideas regarding right, including how it is prior to virtue in important regards. For example, until something distinct from us (such as property) really is ours, it is not ours to give (e.g., as a gift). In chapter 7 (“Kantian Imperfect Duties”), she presents her innovative account of imperfect duties. Here a central aim is to explain why we must not conflate “ends and duties” so that we can see how one “single obligatory end gives rise to a number of duties” (123). In addition, a great amount of time is obviously still devoted to the “posterchild” of imperfect duty, beneficence. However, Herman develops the conventional approach here by, among other things, convincingly proposing that we need to clearly distinguish between “relational beneficence” and beneficence involving strangers (including “humanitarian beneficence”). For example, internal to friendships, gifts and help come with the challenge of making sure that they do not undermine our equality. Wisdom in these regards requires us to understand both a lot about ourselves and our friends as well as how the gift fits into our historical and ongoing, dynamic project of living life together as equals. Gifts can bring us closer together or push us apart, and Herman interestingly suggests that gratitude functions to maintain a good relationship (of equality) when needed assistance is offered and accepted. Finally, in chapter 8 (“Tracking Value and Extending Duties”), Herman presents her take on certain casuistic puzzles as well as imperfect judicial duties. Here she engages, for instance, some of the problems related to lying and self-defense, arguing, first (as she has before), for the exception to the rule when it comes to lying (when doing so does not undermine the end sustained by the general prohibition on lying) and, second (for the first time), that in a fundamental sense, private individuals do not have a right to self-defense (as only the public authority can use coercion rightfully).In part 3, Herman explores some topics central to living in the moral habitat understood as a “dynamic system” (chap. 9) before zooming in on defending “A Right to Housing” (chap. 10) domestically and internationally (refugees). In short, the chapter on housing illustrates how to realize the general Kantian idea of rightful external freedom with regard to this particular issue in our current moral habitats. She then turns to more general ideas or challenges involved in being an agent of ongoing and always incomplete moral change in chapter 11 (“Incompleteness and Moral Change”). Her most general claim here is that “we should accept that there is in principle nothing that counts as a complete or ideal system of duties for human beings. That there is no theoretical point of view from which all that ought to be done is fully determinate or determinable” (213). Among other things, here she reflects on the fact that although we have never had good reasons to restrict moral habitat to certain subsections of human animals, we also have good reasons for why it should not be limited to only human animals and thus exclude other animals. Indeed, she proposes, it is quite possible that in the future we may have reasons also to include robots (artificial intelligence) in various ways. The moral habitat is constantly evolving, and the aim is to become better moral agents of change so that our participation in it helps to transform and improve it. Which is not to say that all the bads in the past or present were or are “just so” (216).In her conclusion “Method and Limits,” Herman underscores that the book as a whole emphasizes that “the notion of innate right is the appropriate starting point for a system of duties, rights, and obligations suited to the condition of human beings” (228). She also stresses that her central aim has been to show how motive must be thought of as “the internal analogue of procedural value—arriving at the right result the right way.” As such, this “notion of motive … is a better fit with psychological theories of human development that see the dynamic changes in the value-objects of affects as essential to the emergence of a healthy human self” (230). Finally, she concludes that another overarching aim has been to show how “imperfect duties are central, substantial parts of the moral terrain, sometimes demanding and often open-ended…. They often provide space for us to bring our critical and imaginative faculties to bear on a developing and dynamic moral system that can have both a creative and a regulatory role in our lives” (230).In the English-speaking world, the topic of imperfect duties has been a core concern for many Kantians in the last few decades, from Onora O’Neill and Thomas E. Hill Jr. to Sarah Holtman and Carol Hay. Similarly, the last couple of decades have seen an explosion in scholarship on Kant’s Doctrine of Right, with libertarian interpretive lines initiated by Sharon Byrd and Joachim Hruscka as well as liberal republican interpretive lines initiated by Thomas Pogge, Ernest Weinrib, and Arthur Ripstein dominating the English-language scholarship. The Moral Habitat is the first of its kind to present an account of imperfect duties that is deeply complementary to works in the liberal republican interpretive tradition, but there is much for all Kantians and non-Kantians to generatively engage in terms of scholarship and philosophical proposals. The Moral Habitat is, as I said at the beginning, a gift to our shared philosophical enterprise; enjoy!","PeriodicalId":48129,"journal":{"name":"PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW","volume":"41 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":2.8000,"publicationDate":"2023-04-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":"0","resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.1215/00318108-10294487","RegionNum":1,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"0","JCRName":"PHILOSOPHY","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0

Abstract

Those who love philosophy books that present new, exciting, and complex theories have been given a gift in Barbara Herman’s The Moral Habitat. In my view, it is also a gift to Kant, since it develops a deeply Kantian account of deliberation as part of showing how perfect and imperfect duties can be seen as working together in a dynamic moral (eco)system of duties of right and of virtue. In the process of doing this, Herman develops a new, intriguing account of imperfect duties and replaces many of Kant’s bad examples with good ones, providing an ideal model for how to argue by example, whether one is Kantian or not. Moreover, by her many intriguing and rich examples, Herman makes many of Kant’s ideas, as well as her revisionary Kantian ideas, available as resources in our shared philosophical practice. Of course, Kantians and others will disagree with some of her arguments and proposals, but many of these discussions yet to come will themselves become important additions to the existing scholarship. Fortunately, too, for a book that presents a new and complex Kantian theory, it does not get bogged down in specific scholarly disputes on particular topics; instead, it stays focused on developing and communicating the big moves, the big picture. Finally, as with all Herman’s brilliant writings, The Moral Habitat is beautifully written—with care, wit, and wisdom. It is, in other words, among the best of gifts: a reliable friend to think with about some very complex and difficult topics—philosophical and human—from now on.The moral habitat is defined as “a made environment, created by and for free and equal persons living together,” and Herman consequently puts “the deliberating and morally active person at the center of a generative moral enterprise” (ix). Herman’s book is furthermore divided into three parts: part 1 “Three Imperfect Duties,” part 2 “Kantian Resources,” and part 3 “Living in the Moral Habitat.” Part 1 serves to rid readers of some ingrained expectations they are likely to have of Kantian discussions of imperfect duty, such as the expectation that this will mostly be a discussion of beneficence or that it will assume a specific, historically prominent interpretation of motive or incentive. In these ways, Herman helps us to open our philosophical minds and stimulates our philosophical curiosity and imagination. More specifically, after the first chapter, focused on “Framing the Question (What We Can Learn From Imperfect Duties),” Herman provides chapter-length discussions of gratitude, giving, and due care (chaps. 2, 3, and 4, resp.). Her main strategy throughout these chapters is to develop each idea from the bottom up, working from many rich and intriguing examples to a summary section in each chapter—called “middle work”—where she draws our (philosophically trained minds’) attention to her main findings. For example, the main focus of chapter 3 is the puzzle of why giving too much—such as paying too much when repaying a loan or giving too much as a gift—causes damage. In the “middle work” section following these examples, Herman then draws out some metanormative claims about how permissibility and wrongness relate to one another, with a special focus on her claim throughout this chapter that there is a “possible consistency of not impermissible and morally wrong” (43).Herman’s strategy in this first part is effective and productive. It shows us that figuring out what to do in any situation (good deliberation) requires us to pay attention to its complexity—an interpretation of Kant’s statement that wisdom requires “judgement sharpened by experience” (Kant 1996)—and to how many rights, duties, and obligations interweave in specific situations. The examples also help everyone to be ready for the more philosophically sophisticated discussions in the “middle work” sections and, of course, for the rest of the book. Herman’s strategy here also helps rid us of the bad habit of looking for simple solutions to complex questions—whether our preferred simplifying method is to focus on one, allegedly core, example (of Kant’s) or one principle, or one interpretation thereof (such as the so-called categorical imperative procedure). Living life well, on our own and together with others, is much more difficult than this at any given moment and through time (as the circumstances of our lives evolve and change). In these ways—and throughout the book—Herman shows us how to deliberate within the Kantian framework; Aristotle is no longer the only (classical) alternative in town on the topic of good deliberation.Part 2 zooms in on Kantian practical philosophical resources, especially as they are found in, and can be further developed from, the Groundwork for the Metaphysics of Morals and The Metaphysics of Morals. Herman’s overall aim here is to “introduce and argue for a revisionary interpretation of Kant’s ethics (broadly construed)… [as] guided by two lodestars: that the resulting reading be convincingly Kant’s ethics, in both letter and spirit, and that the revision justify itself by giving us a better theory, in its own terms and in ours” (73). More specifically, chapter 6 (“The Kantian System of Duties”) presents Herman’s interpretation of many basic interpretive and philosophical ideas regarding right, including how it is prior to virtue in important regards. For example, until something distinct from us (such as property) really is ours, it is not ours to give (e.g., as a gift). In chapter 7 (“Kantian Imperfect Duties”), she presents her innovative account of imperfect duties. Here a central aim is to explain why we must not conflate “ends and duties” so that we can see how one “single obligatory end gives rise to a number of duties” (123). In addition, a great amount of time is obviously still devoted to the “posterchild” of imperfect duty, beneficence. However, Herman develops the conventional approach here by, among other things, convincingly proposing that we need to clearly distinguish between “relational beneficence” and beneficence involving strangers (including “humanitarian beneficence”). For example, internal to friendships, gifts and help come with the challenge of making sure that they do not undermine our equality. Wisdom in these regards requires us to understand both a lot about ourselves and our friends as well as how the gift fits into our historical and ongoing, dynamic project of living life together as equals. Gifts can bring us closer together or push us apart, and Herman interestingly suggests that gratitude functions to maintain a good relationship (of equality) when needed assistance is offered and accepted. Finally, in chapter 8 (“Tracking Value and Extending Duties”), Herman presents her take on certain casuistic puzzles as well as imperfect judicial duties. Here she engages, for instance, some of the problems related to lying and self-defense, arguing, first (as she has before), for the exception to the rule when it comes to lying (when doing so does not undermine the end sustained by the general prohibition on lying) and, second (for the first time), that in a fundamental sense, private individuals do not have a right to self-defense (as only the public authority can use coercion rightfully).In part 3, Herman explores some topics central to living in the moral habitat understood as a “dynamic system” (chap. 9) before zooming in on defending “A Right to Housing” (chap. 10) domestically and internationally (refugees). In short, the chapter on housing illustrates how to realize the general Kantian idea of rightful external freedom with regard to this particular issue in our current moral habitats. She then turns to more general ideas or challenges involved in being an agent of ongoing and always incomplete moral change in chapter 11 (“Incompleteness and Moral Change”). Her most general claim here is that “we should accept that there is in principle nothing that counts as a complete or ideal system of duties for human beings. That there is no theoretical point of view from which all that ought to be done is fully determinate or determinable” (213). Among other things, here she reflects on the fact that although we have never had good reasons to restrict moral habitat to certain subsections of human animals, we also have good reasons for why it should not be limited to only human animals and thus exclude other animals. Indeed, she proposes, it is quite possible that in the future we may have reasons also to include robots (artificial intelligence) in various ways. The moral habitat is constantly evolving, and the aim is to become better moral agents of change so that our participation in it helps to transform and improve it. Which is not to say that all the bads in the past or present were or are “just so” (216).In her conclusion “Method and Limits,” Herman underscores that the book as a whole emphasizes that “the notion of innate right is the appropriate starting point for a system of duties, rights, and obligations suited to the condition of human beings” (228). She also stresses that her central aim has been to show how motive must be thought of as “the internal analogue of procedural value—arriving at the right result the right way.” As such, this “notion of motive … is a better fit with psychological theories of human development that see the dynamic changes in the value-objects of affects as essential to the emergence of a healthy human self” (230). Finally, she concludes that another overarching aim has been to show how “imperfect duties are central, substantial parts of the moral terrain, sometimes demanding and often open-ended…. They often provide space for us to bring our critical and imaginative faculties to bear on a developing and dynamic moral system that can have both a creative and a regulatory role in our lives” (230).In the English-speaking world, the topic of imperfect duties has been a core concern for many Kantians in the last few decades, from Onora O’Neill and Thomas E. Hill Jr. to Sarah Holtman and Carol Hay. Similarly, the last couple of decades have seen an explosion in scholarship on Kant’s Doctrine of Right, with libertarian interpretive lines initiated by Sharon Byrd and Joachim Hruscka as well as liberal republican interpretive lines initiated by Thomas Pogge, Ernest Weinrib, and Arthur Ripstein dominating the English-language scholarship. The Moral Habitat is the first of its kind to present an account of imperfect duties that is deeply complementary to works in the liberal republican interpretive tradition, but there is much for all Kantians and non-Kantians to generatively engage in terms of scholarship and philosophical proposals. The Moral Habitat is, as I said at the beginning, a gift to our shared philosophical enterprise; enjoy!
道德栖息地
芭芭拉·赫尔曼的《道德栖息地》给那些喜欢哲学书籍的人带来了一份礼物,这些书提出了新的、令人兴奋的、复杂的理论。在我看来,这也是给康德的一份礼物,因为它发展了一种深刻的康德式思考,作为展示完美和不完美的义务如何在权利和美德义务的动态道德(生态)系统中共同作用的一部分。在此过程中,赫尔曼发展了一种新的、有趣的关于不完全义务的解释,并用好的例子取代了康德的许多坏例子,为如何通过例子进行论证提供了一个理想的模型,无论一个人是否是康德的。此外,通过她许多有趣而丰富的例子,赫尔曼使康德的许多思想,以及她修正的康德思想,成为我们共同的哲学实践的资源。当然,康德主义者和其他人将不同意她的一些论点和建议,但许多这些讨论尚未到来,它们本身将成为现有学术的重要补充。同样幸运的是,作为一本呈现全新而复杂的康德理论的书,它没有陷入特定主题的特定学术争论;相反,它专注于发展和沟通大动作,大局。最后,就像赫尔曼所有杰出的作品一样,《道德栖息地》写得很漂亮——用心、机智和智慧。换句话说,它是最好的礼物之一:从现在开始,它是一个值得信赖的朋友,可以一起思考一些非常复杂和困难的话题——哲学的和人类的。道德栖息地被定义为“一个由共同生活的自由平等的人创造并为之创造的环境”,因此赫尔曼将“深思熟虑和道德活跃的人置于生成性道德事业的中心”(ix)。赫尔曼的书进一步分为三个部分:第一部分“三种不完美的义务”,第二部分“康德的资源”和第三部分“生活在道德栖息地”。第一部分是为了让读者摆脱一些根深蒂固的期望,他们可能会对康德的不完美义务的讨论产生一些期望,比如期望这将主要是对善行的讨论,或者它将假设一个特定的,历史上突出的动机或激励的解释。通过这些方式,赫尔曼帮助我们打开了哲学思维,激发了我们的哲学好奇心和想象力。更具体地说,在第一章聚焦于“构建问题(我们可以从不完美的责任中学到什么)”之后,赫尔曼提供了一章关于感恩、给予和应有的照顾的讨论(第11章)。第2、3、4条)。在这些章节中,她的主要策略是从下到上发展每个观点,从许多丰富而有趣的例子到每章的总结部分——称为“中间工作”——在那里,她把我们(受过哲学训练的人)的注意力吸引到她的主要发现上。例如,第三章的主要焦点是为什么给予太多——比如在偿还贷款时付出太多,或者作为礼物给予太多——会造成损害。在这些例子之后的“中间工作”部分,赫尔曼随后提出了一些关于允许和错误如何相互关联的隐喻性主张,并特别关注她在本章中的主张,即“不允许和道德错误之间存在可能的一致性”(43)。赫尔曼在第一部分的策略是有效和富有成效的。它告诉我们,在任何情况下想要做什么(好的深思熟虑)都需要我们注意它的复杂性——这是对康德关于智慧需要“经验磨练的判断”的解释(康德1996)——以及在特定情况下有多少权利、责任和义务交织在一起。这些例子还帮助每个人为“中间工作”部分中更复杂的哲学讨论做好准备,当然,也为本书的其余部分做好准备。赫尔曼在这里的策略也帮助我们摆脱了为复杂问题寻找简单解决方案的坏习惯——无论我们喜欢的简化方法是专注于一个,所谓的核心,例子(康德的)还是一个原则,或一个解释(如所谓的定言命令程序)。在任何特定的时刻和时间(随着我们生活环境的发展和变化),我们自己或与他人一起过好生活都比这困难得多。赫尔曼通过这些方式——贯穿全书——向我们展示了如何在康德的框架内进行思考;亚里士多德不再是关于深思熟虑这个话题的唯一(古典)选择。第二部分聚焦于康德的实践哲学资源,特别是在《道德形而上学的基础》和《道德形而上学》中可以找到并可以进一步发展的资源。
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
求助全文
约1分钟内获得全文 求助全文
来源期刊
PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW
PHILOSOPHICAL REVIEW PHILOSOPHY-
CiteScore
7.40
自引率
0.00%
发文量
17
期刊介绍: In continuous publication since 1892, the Philosophical Review has a long-standing reputation for excellence and has published many papers now considered classics in the field, such as W. V. O. Quine"s “Two Dogmas of Empiricism,” Thomas Nagel"s “What Is It Like to Be a Bat?” and the early work of John Rawls. The journal aims to publish original scholarly work in all areas of analytic philosophy, with an emphasis on material of general interest to academic philosophers, and is one of the few journals in the discipline to publish book reviews.
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
确定
请完成安全验证×
copy
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
右上角分享
点击右上角分享
0
联系我们:info@booksci.cn Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。 Copyright © 2023 布克学术 All rights reserved.
京ICP备2023020795号-1
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术官方微信