The Imagination in Hume’s Philosophy: The Canvas of the Mind by Timothy M. Costelloe

IF 0.3 4区 哲学 0 PHILOSOPHY
Hume Studies Pub Date : 2023-04-01 DOI:10.1353/hms.2023.0004
Saul Traiger
{"title":"The Imagination in Hume’s Philosophy: The Canvas of the Mind by Timothy M. Costelloe","authors":"Saul Traiger","doi":"10.1353/hms.2023.0004","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"Reviewed by: The Imagination in Hume’s Philosophy: The Canvas of the Mind by Timothy M. Costelloe Saul Traiger Timothy M. Costelloe. The Imagination in Hume’s Philosophy: The Canvas of the Mind. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press, 2018. Pp. xv + 312. Hardback. ISBN: 9781474436397. $107.00. If anything about Hume’s philosophy can be characterized as widely accepted, it is that the imagination is front and center in Hume’s account of the mind. The aim of Timothy Costelloe’s book is to fully develop the observation, that the imagination, as Hume understands it, is “the canvas of the mind.” Costelloe amply demonstrates that the imagination is a broad canvas, ranging from Hume’s epistemology and metaphysics, to his aesthetics, moral and political philosophy, history, philosophy of religion, and his general conception of philosophy itself. Seven substantial chapters cover these areas, and show how Hume takes the imagination to play a pivotal role in each. One of the many strengths of this book is that Costelloe responsibly mines the secondary literature, carefully explaining the interpretations he seconds and those he finds wanting. The attention to the relevant secondary literature is apparent from the start, where Costelloe laments the surprising dearth of book-length treatments of Hume on the imagination, but helpfully highlights both the lesser known Hume-centric monographs on the imagination by Furlong and Wilbanks, as well as more widely read interpretations. The introductory chapter makes important distinctions and introduces some main concepts. Hume differentiates the imagination’s “combinatory power” from its “creative power.” While the uninhibited ability to concatenate ideas might also be seen as a creative act, Costelloe sees the creative power where the imagination [End Page 173] “generates a class of ideas—‘fictions’ of a certain sort—independent of experience and according to its own inner logic” (21). This characterization makes sense when viewing the imagination’s function as directed towards a goal, such as achieving coherence or creating an aesthetically pleasing effect. Costelloe suggests that achieving an aesthetically pleasing effect is an element in any exercise of the imagination’s creative power. The imagination creates easy transitions among ideas where there were none, where doing so is pleasurable, or aided by the passions. Costelloe introduces his account of Hume’s fictions as errors of the imagination whereby ideas are formed in a manner different from the standard derivation from antecedent impressions. He insists, helpfully, that fictions are not illusions, but rather errors of a different kind. Though both involve error, fictions, unlike illusions, are not described in terms of jest or irony (30). Though he acknowledges that Hume does not describe any fictions as “artificial,” Costelloe finds it helpful to draw a distinction between natural and artificial fictions. Natural fictions are generated without reflection. Artificial fictions, such as those created by poets and philosophers, issue from “the voluntary act of imagination” (31). Costelloe holds that artificial fictions “are rarely taken to refer to objects with real existence and that any professed belief is really a matter of people being persuaded of something and taking the ideas in question as having real referents, thus only lending themselves to their existence for one reason or another” (31). This is a bit unclear. Certainly, poetic fictions are voluntary creations not intended to refer to real objects. But substance, and the double existence of ideas and external objects, as philosophical fictions, surely both involve belief and the corresponding existential commitments on the part of the philosophers who are committed to them. It is also difficult to see the purported contrast between belief and taking ideas to have real referents. Chapter 2, on metaphysics, is the longest chapter in the book, and it addresses the fictions of the imagination in Hume’s account of space and time, continued and distinct existence, liberty and necessity, and personal identity. Costelloe is sensitive to the worry that classifying Hume’s subject in Book 1 of the Treatise as metaphysics may appear to be slighting the central epistemological concerns and failing to appreciate Hume’s nascent cognitive psychology. Such worries fall away as Costelloe explores the roles that the imagination plays in the formation of our conception of duration without change, and the identity...","PeriodicalId":29761,"journal":{"name":"Hume Studies","volume":"57 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.3000,"publicationDate":"2023-04-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":"0","resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"Hume Studies","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.1353/hms.2023.0004","RegionNum":4,"RegionCategory":"哲学","ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"0","JCRName":"PHILOSOPHY","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0

Abstract

Reviewed by: The Imagination in Hume’s Philosophy: The Canvas of the Mind by Timothy M. Costelloe Saul Traiger Timothy M. Costelloe. The Imagination in Hume’s Philosophy: The Canvas of the Mind. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press, 2018. Pp. xv + 312. Hardback. ISBN: 9781474436397. $107.00. If anything about Hume’s philosophy can be characterized as widely accepted, it is that the imagination is front and center in Hume’s account of the mind. The aim of Timothy Costelloe’s book is to fully develop the observation, that the imagination, as Hume understands it, is “the canvas of the mind.” Costelloe amply demonstrates that the imagination is a broad canvas, ranging from Hume’s epistemology and metaphysics, to his aesthetics, moral and political philosophy, history, philosophy of religion, and his general conception of philosophy itself. Seven substantial chapters cover these areas, and show how Hume takes the imagination to play a pivotal role in each. One of the many strengths of this book is that Costelloe responsibly mines the secondary literature, carefully explaining the interpretations he seconds and those he finds wanting. The attention to the relevant secondary literature is apparent from the start, where Costelloe laments the surprising dearth of book-length treatments of Hume on the imagination, but helpfully highlights both the lesser known Hume-centric monographs on the imagination by Furlong and Wilbanks, as well as more widely read interpretations. The introductory chapter makes important distinctions and introduces some main concepts. Hume differentiates the imagination’s “combinatory power” from its “creative power.” While the uninhibited ability to concatenate ideas might also be seen as a creative act, Costelloe sees the creative power where the imagination [End Page 173] “generates a class of ideas—‘fictions’ of a certain sort—independent of experience and according to its own inner logic” (21). This characterization makes sense when viewing the imagination’s function as directed towards a goal, such as achieving coherence or creating an aesthetically pleasing effect. Costelloe suggests that achieving an aesthetically pleasing effect is an element in any exercise of the imagination’s creative power. The imagination creates easy transitions among ideas where there were none, where doing so is pleasurable, or aided by the passions. Costelloe introduces his account of Hume’s fictions as errors of the imagination whereby ideas are formed in a manner different from the standard derivation from antecedent impressions. He insists, helpfully, that fictions are not illusions, but rather errors of a different kind. Though both involve error, fictions, unlike illusions, are not described in terms of jest or irony (30). Though he acknowledges that Hume does not describe any fictions as “artificial,” Costelloe finds it helpful to draw a distinction between natural and artificial fictions. Natural fictions are generated without reflection. Artificial fictions, such as those created by poets and philosophers, issue from “the voluntary act of imagination” (31). Costelloe holds that artificial fictions “are rarely taken to refer to objects with real existence and that any professed belief is really a matter of people being persuaded of something and taking the ideas in question as having real referents, thus only lending themselves to their existence for one reason or another” (31). This is a bit unclear. Certainly, poetic fictions are voluntary creations not intended to refer to real objects. But substance, and the double existence of ideas and external objects, as philosophical fictions, surely both involve belief and the corresponding existential commitments on the part of the philosophers who are committed to them. It is also difficult to see the purported contrast between belief and taking ideas to have real referents. Chapter 2, on metaphysics, is the longest chapter in the book, and it addresses the fictions of the imagination in Hume’s account of space and time, continued and distinct existence, liberty and necessity, and personal identity. Costelloe is sensitive to the worry that classifying Hume’s subject in Book 1 of the Treatise as metaphysics may appear to be slighting the central epistemological concerns and failing to appreciate Hume’s nascent cognitive psychology. Such worries fall away as Costelloe explores the roles that the imagination plays in the formation of our conception of duration without change, and the identity...
休谟哲学中的想象:蒂莫西·m·科斯特洛《心灵的画布
书评:《休谟哲学中的想象:心灵的画布》作者:蒂莫西·m·科斯特洛休谟哲学中的想象:心灵的画布。爱丁堡:爱丁堡大学出版社,2018。第15页+ 312页。精装版。ISBN: 9781474436397。107.00美元。如果说休谟的哲学有什么特点是被广泛接受的,那就是想象是休谟对心灵的描述的前沿和中心。蒂莫西·科斯特洛(Timothy costello)这本书的目的是充分发展这一观察,即想象,正如休谟所理解的那样,是“心灵的画布”。科斯特洛充分展示了想象是一个广阔的画布,从休谟的认识论和形而上学,到他的美学,道德和政治哲学,历史,宗教哲学,以及他对哲学本身的一般概念。七个实质性的章节涵盖了这些领域,并展示了休谟如何在每个领域发挥想象力的关键作用。这本书的众多优点之一是,科斯特洛负责地挖掘二手文献,仔细解释他认可的解释和他发现的不足之处。对相关二手文献的关注从一开始就很明显,科斯特洛在书中哀叹休谟在想象方面的著述少得惊人,但他也很有帮助地强调了弗朗和威尔班克斯所著的以休谟为中心的、鲜为人知的关于想象的专著,以及更广泛阅读的解释。导论部分做了重要的区分,并介绍了一些主要概念。休谟区分了想象力的“组合能力”和“创造力”。虽然这种不受约束的将想法串联起来的能力也可以被视为一种创造性的行为,但科斯特洛认为,想象力“产生了一类想法——某种类型的‘虚构’——独立于经验,并根据其自身的内在逻辑”(21)。当把想象力的功能看作是指向一个目标时,比如实现连贯或创造一种美学上令人愉悦的效果,这种特征是有道理的。科斯特洛认为,实现美学上的愉悦效果是任何想象力创造力练习的一个要素。想象可以在没有想法的地方轻松地转换,这样做是愉快的,或者是在激情的帮助下。科斯特洛介绍了他对休谟小说的描述,认为它是想象的错误,在这种错误中,思想以一种不同于先前印象的标准衍生方式形成。他坚持认为,小说不是幻觉,而是另一种错误。虽然两者都涉及错误,但小说与幻想不同,不会用玩笑或讽刺来描述(30)。尽管科斯特洛承认休谟并没有将任何小说描述为“人造的”,但他认为区分自然小说和人造小说是有帮助的。自然的虚构是不经思考而产生的。虚构的小说,如诗人和哲学家创作的小说,来自“想象的自发行为”(31)。科斯特洛认为,人为的虚构“很少被认为是指真实存在的物体,任何公开宣称的信仰实际上都是人们被说服相信某件事,并将所讨论的想法视为具有真实的参照物,因此只是出于这样或那样的原因才使自己存在”(31)。这有点不清楚。当然,诗歌小说是自愿创作的,不打算参考真实的对象。但是实体,以及理念和外部客体的双重存在,作为哲学的虚构,当然都涉及信仰和相应的哲学家的存在性承诺。也很难看出所谓的信仰和把思想当作真实的参照物之间的对比。第二章是关于形而上学的,是书中最长的一章,它讲述了休谟对空间和时间,持续和独特的存在,自由和必然性,以及个人身份的描述中想象的虚构。科斯特洛对将休谟在《人性论》第一卷中的主题归类为形而上学的担忧很敏感,这可能会显得轻视了核心的认识论问题,也未能理解休谟新生的认知心理学。当科斯特洛探索想象力在我们的“不变的持续时间”概念的形成过程中所起的作用时,这些担忧就消失了。
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
求助全文
约1分钟内获得全文 求助全文
来源期刊
CiteScore
0.20
自引率
0.00%
发文量
0
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
确定
请完成安全验证×
copy
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
右上角分享
点击右上角分享
0
联系我们:info@booksci.cn Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。 Copyright © 2023 布克学术 All rights reserved.
京ICP备2023020795号-1
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术官方微信