{"title":"Default Rules and the Inevitability of Paternalism","authors":"L. Zanitelli","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.1346497","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"In a paper published some years ago, Cass R. Sunstein and Richard Thaler argue for a sort of soft paternalism referred to as “libertarian paternalism.” Relying on cognitive findings regarding the status quo bias, one of Sunstein and Thaler’s central claims is that default rules can be used for paternalistic purposes, given people’s proneness to adhere to what is established by these rules. This strategy is also called ‘libertarian’, since parties remain free to contract around the paternalistic rule if they wish. Considering the influence of default rules on parties’ behavior, Sunstein and Thaler affirm that soft paternalism is not just defensible but inevitable, inasmuch as any adopted rule will affect people’s choices. This is an audacious conclusion, which surprisingly has attracted little attention from critics of the paternalism of behavioral law and economics The aim of this paper is to assess the alleged inevitability of paternalism. After examining the distinction between hard and soft paternalism, it sustains that, in order to validate Sunstein and Thaler’s claim, paternalism has to be broadly equated to “influencing behavior”. A more restricted definition of paternalism, according to which an act or norm is paternalistic only if it tries to advance someone else’s objective wellbeing, leads to the conclusion that default rules, whose end is not necessarily to protect parties’ interests, are not paternalistic by definition. Taking into account the potential, but not inherent, paternalism of default rules, the last Section of the paper comments on three criticisms regarding the interventionist character of behavioral law and economics. The first criticism refers to the fact that public authorities are vulnerable to the same cognitive pitfalls of the individuals whose activity is regulated; the second concerns the redistributive effects of paternalism involving rational and irrational people; and the third one warns against the “slippery slope” consequences of soft paternalism, i.e., the risk that milder paternalistic measures, as those supported by Sunstein and Thaler, give rise to more intrusive forms of state intervention.","PeriodicalId":393808,"journal":{"name":"Berkeley Program in Law & Economics","volume":"365 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0000,"publicationDate":"2009-05-27","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":"5","resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"Berkeley Program in Law & Economics","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.1346497","RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":null,"ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"","JCRName":"","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 5
Abstract
In a paper published some years ago, Cass R. Sunstein and Richard Thaler argue for a sort of soft paternalism referred to as “libertarian paternalism.” Relying on cognitive findings regarding the status quo bias, one of Sunstein and Thaler’s central claims is that default rules can be used for paternalistic purposes, given people’s proneness to adhere to what is established by these rules. This strategy is also called ‘libertarian’, since parties remain free to contract around the paternalistic rule if they wish. Considering the influence of default rules on parties’ behavior, Sunstein and Thaler affirm that soft paternalism is not just defensible but inevitable, inasmuch as any adopted rule will affect people’s choices. This is an audacious conclusion, which surprisingly has attracted little attention from critics of the paternalism of behavioral law and economics The aim of this paper is to assess the alleged inevitability of paternalism. After examining the distinction between hard and soft paternalism, it sustains that, in order to validate Sunstein and Thaler’s claim, paternalism has to be broadly equated to “influencing behavior”. A more restricted definition of paternalism, according to which an act or norm is paternalistic only if it tries to advance someone else’s objective wellbeing, leads to the conclusion that default rules, whose end is not necessarily to protect parties’ interests, are not paternalistic by definition. Taking into account the potential, but not inherent, paternalism of default rules, the last Section of the paper comments on three criticisms regarding the interventionist character of behavioral law and economics. The first criticism refers to the fact that public authorities are vulnerable to the same cognitive pitfalls of the individuals whose activity is regulated; the second concerns the redistributive effects of paternalism involving rational and irrational people; and the third one warns against the “slippery slope” consequences of soft paternalism, i.e., the risk that milder paternalistic measures, as those supported by Sunstein and Thaler, give rise to more intrusive forms of state intervention.
在几年前发表的一篇论文中,卡斯·r·桑斯坦(Cass R. Sunstein)和理查德·塞勒(Richard Thaler)主张一种被称为“自由意志式家长制”的软家长制。基于对现状偏见的认知发现,桑斯坦和塞勒的核心主张之一是,鉴于人们倾向于遵守这些规则所建立的东西,默认规则可以被用于家长式的目的。这种策略也被称为“自由意志主义”,因为如果各方愿意,他们仍然可以自由地围绕家长式统治达成协议。考虑到默认规则对当事人行为的影响,桑斯坦和塞勒断言,软家长制不仅是可辩护的,而且是不可避免的,因为任何采用的规则都会影响人们的选择。这是一个大胆的结论,令人惊讶的是,它几乎没有引起行为法学和经济学中家长制的批评者的注意。本文的目的是评估所谓的家长制的必然性。在研究了硬家长制和软家长制之间的区别之后,它坚持认为,为了验证桑斯坦和塞勒的说法,家长制必须大致等同于“影响行为”。家长式作风的一个更严格的定义是,只有当一项行为或规范试图促进他人的客观福祉时,它才是家长式作风。根据这种定义,默认规则的目的不一定是保护各方的利益,从定义上讲,它不是家长式作风。考虑到默认规则的潜在而非固有的家长式作风,本文的最后一节对关于行为法和经济学的干预主义特征的三种批评进行了评论。第一种批评指的是这样一个事实,即公共当局容易受到与活动受管制的个人相同的认知陷阱的影响;第二个是关于家长制的再分配效应,涉及理性和非理性的人;第三篇则对软家长制的“滑坡效应”提出了警告,即桑斯坦和塞勒支持的温和家长制措施有可能导致更具侵入性的国家干预形式。