{"title":"Bodies as behavior","authors":"John M. Oksanish","doi":"10.1093/oso/9780190696986.003.0006","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"The Dinocrates-Alexander episode of book 2 supplies the reader with a complex heuristic for differentiating good architects from bad. Vitruvius claims to rely on his knowledge and writing in anticipation of his own success, whereas he attributes Dinocrates’ renown to an attractive bodily appearance. A close intertextual reading of the passage threaded through Livy 1 suggests that Alexander and Dinocrates violate the ideal architect–autocrat relationship. The manner in which one interprets the episode indicates whether one can distinguish altruism from ambitio and the like. Alexander’s appetitious reaction to Dinocrates and his body is further problematized by the latter’s nudity and evocation of Hercules and athletic victors. Discussions in the rhetorical handbooks indicate that arguments concerning a plaintiff’s or defendant’s bodily state can support arguments about his character. The handbooks seem to presume a widespread valorization of what the Greeks would call καλοκἀγαθία, but there is an implicit acknowledgment that beauty dissimulates vice. The athletic and/or gladiatorial body is therefore a particular locus of contestation and controversy, as Cicero’s (and Sallust’s) depictions of Catiline show. On the Greek side, writers as early as Tyrtaeus and Xenophanes had suggested that wisdom is better than strength. Isocrates frames the issue politically, and Vitruvius takes it one step further. Following the Roman handbooks that viewed the cultivation of bodily attributes (vs. the fortuitous possession of those attributes) as the primary signifier of character, Vitruvius suggests that athletes are ethically and politically bankrupt, while writers deserve triumphs and apotheosis. Archimedes, Socrates, and even Vitruvius himself provide counterexamples.","PeriodicalId":242293,"journal":{"name":"Vitruvian Man","volume":"9 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0000,"publicationDate":"2019-11-14","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":"0","resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"Vitruvian Man","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.1093/oso/9780190696986.003.0006","RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":null,"ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"","JCRName":"","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0
Abstract
The Dinocrates-Alexander episode of book 2 supplies the reader with a complex heuristic for differentiating good architects from bad. Vitruvius claims to rely on his knowledge and writing in anticipation of his own success, whereas he attributes Dinocrates’ renown to an attractive bodily appearance. A close intertextual reading of the passage threaded through Livy 1 suggests that Alexander and Dinocrates violate the ideal architect–autocrat relationship. The manner in which one interprets the episode indicates whether one can distinguish altruism from ambitio and the like. Alexander’s appetitious reaction to Dinocrates and his body is further problematized by the latter’s nudity and evocation of Hercules and athletic victors. Discussions in the rhetorical handbooks indicate that arguments concerning a plaintiff’s or defendant’s bodily state can support arguments about his character. The handbooks seem to presume a widespread valorization of what the Greeks would call καλοκἀγαθία, but there is an implicit acknowledgment that beauty dissimulates vice. The athletic and/or gladiatorial body is therefore a particular locus of contestation and controversy, as Cicero’s (and Sallust’s) depictions of Catiline show. On the Greek side, writers as early as Tyrtaeus and Xenophanes had suggested that wisdom is better than strength. Isocrates frames the issue politically, and Vitruvius takes it one step further. Following the Roman handbooks that viewed the cultivation of bodily attributes (vs. the fortuitous possession of those attributes) as the primary signifier of character, Vitruvius suggests that athletes are ethically and politically bankrupt, while writers deserve triumphs and apotheosis. Archimedes, Socrates, and even Vitruvius himself provide counterexamples.
第2本书的Dinocrates-Alexander章节为读者提供了一个区分好建筑师和坏建筑师的复杂启发式。维特鲁威声称依靠他的知识和写作来期待自己的成功,而他把迪诺克拉特的名声归功于他迷人的外表。对《李维1》中贯穿的段落进行仔细的互文阅读表明,亚历山大和狄诺克拉底违反了理想的建筑师与独裁者的关系。一个人解释这一事件的方式表明他是否能够区分利他主义和野心等。亚历山大对迪诺克拉底和他的身体的食欲反应被后者的裸体和对赫拉克勒斯和运动胜利者的唤起进一步问题化。修辞手册中的讨论表明,关于原告或被告身体状况的论点可以支持关于其性格的论点。这些手册似乎假定了希腊人所说的καλοκ ο γαθ末路α′的普遍价值,但其中隐含着一种承认,即美可以掩饰罪恶。因此,正如西塞罗(和萨洛斯特)对卡提林的描绘所显示的那样,运动和/或角斗士的身体是争论和争议的特殊场所。在希腊方面,早在提尔泰乌斯和色诺芬尼的作家就提出智慧胜过力量。伊索克拉底从政治角度阐述了这个问题,而维特鲁威则更进一步。根据罗马手册将身体素质的培养(相对于偶然拥有这些素质)视为性格的主要象征,维特鲁威认为运动员在道德和政治上都是破产的,而作家应该获得胜利和崇拜。阿基米德、苏格拉底,甚至维特鲁威本人都提供了反例。