The Social Epistemology of Consensus and Dissent

Boaz Miller
{"title":"The Social Epistemology of Consensus and Dissent","authors":"Boaz Miller","doi":"10.4324/9781315717937-23","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"This paper reviews current debates in social epistemology about the relations between knowledge and consensus. These relations are philosophically interesting on their own, but also have practical consequences, as consensus takes an increasingly significant role in informing public decision making. The paper addresses the following questions. When is a consensus attributable to an epistemic community? Under what conditions may we legitimately infer that a consensual view is knowledge-based or otherwise epistemically justified? Should consensus be the aim of scientific inquiry, and if so, what kind of consensus? How should dissent be handled? It is argued that a legitimate inference that a theory is correct from the fact that there is a scientific consensus on it requires taking into consideration both cognitive properties of the theory as well as social properties of the consensus. The last section of the paper reviews computational models of consensus formation. Consensus plays an increasingly growing role in public life. The National Institute of Health (NIH) and the Intergovernmental Panel on Climate Change (IPCC) formulate expert consensus statements to provide authoritative answers to disputed questions. The “Danish Citizen Consensus Model” is used for assessing societal dimensions of science and technology (Medlock et al, 2007; Horst 2008; Einsiedel et al. 2001). Wikipedia promotes consensus for achieving neutrality and verifiability (Wikipedia 2017). Scientific consensus is deferred to when arbitrating between rival experts in legal trials. But when we think about the relations between knowledge and consensus, two conflicting intuitions arise. On the one hand, since when is truth determined by numbers? Are we back to the notorious Indiana House of Representatives “Pi Bill” of 1897, which redefined Pi by majority voting? (Hallerberg 1977) Wasn’t Galileo right although his views contradicted common wisdom? On the other hand, for every Galileo, there are hundreds of misguided contrarians, forgotten by history. Is everybody wrong and only you are right? Current social epistemology of consensus and dissent sorts out these conflicting intuitions. 1 Social epistemologists distinguish between knowledge-based consensus and mere agreement, explore the relations between consensus and the aims of inquiry, and distinguish legitimate from illegitimate dissent. Section 1 concerns the attribution of consensus to an epistemic community. Section 2 reviews accounts of knowledge-based or epistemically justified consensus. Section 3 addresses consensus as an aim of inquiry and the normative status of dissent. Section 4 reviews computational models of consensus. 1. When Does a Consensus Exist? Deciding whether a consensus exists is not always trivial. To do so, we need to assess the scope of and depth of the agreement. Start with scope. Tucker (2003, 509-510) argues that a 1 In philosophy of science until the early 1980s, scientific consensus was addressed mostly in the context of Kuhn’s (1962/1970) The Structure of the Scientific Revolutions (See Wray in this volume). For a classic account of the interplay between data, theory, method, and rational consensus, see Laudan (1984).","PeriodicalId":438715,"journal":{"name":"The Routledge Handbook of Social Epistemology","volume":"1 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0000,"publicationDate":"2019-07-19","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":"9","resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"The Routledge Handbook of Social Epistemology","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.4324/9781315717937-23","RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":null,"ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"","JCRName":"","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 9

Abstract

This paper reviews current debates in social epistemology about the relations between knowledge and consensus. These relations are philosophically interesting on their own, but also have practical consequences, as consensus takes an increasingly significant role in informing public decision making. The paper addresses the following questions. When is a consensus attributable to an epistemic community? Under what conditions may we legitimately infer that a consensual view is knowledge-based or otherwise epistemically justified? Should consensus be the aim of scientific inquiry, and if so, what kind of consensus? How should dissent be handled? It is argued that a legitimate inference that a theory is correct from the fact that there is a scientific consensus on it requires taking into consideration both cognitive properties of the theory as well as social properties of the consensus. The last section of the paper reviews computational models of consensus formation. Consensus plays an increasingly growing role in public life. The National Institute of Health (NIH) and the Intergovernmental Panel on Climate Change (IPCC) formulate expert consensus statements to provide authoritative answers to disputed questions. The “Danish Citizen Consensus Model” is used for assessing societal dimensions of science and technology (Medlock et al, 2007; Horst 2008; Einsiedel et al. 2001). Wikipedia promotes consensus for achieving neutrality and verifiability (Wikipedia 2017). Scientific consensus is deferred to when arbitrating between rival experts in legal trials. But when we think about the relations between knowledge and consensus, two conflicting intuitions arise. On the one hand, since when is truth determined by numbers? Are we back to the notorious Indiana House of Representatives “Pi Bill” of 1897, which redefined Pi by majority voting? (Hallerberg 1977) Wasn’t Galileo right although his views contradicted common wisdom? On the other hand, for every Galileo, there are hundreds of misguided contrarians, forgotten by history. Is everybody wrong and only you are right? Current social epistemology of consensus and dissent sorts out these conflicting intuitions. 1 Social epistemologists distinguish between knowledge-based consensus and mere agreement, explore the relations between consensus and the aims of inquiry, and distinguish legitimate from illegitimate dissent. Section 1 concerns the attribution of consensus to an epistemic community. Section 2 reviews accounts of knowledge-based or epistemically justified consensus. Section 3 addresses consensus as an aim of inquiry and the normative status of dissent. Section 4 reviews computational models of consensus. 1. When Does a Consensus Exist? Deciding whether a consensus exists is not always trivial. To do so, we need to assess the scope of and depth of the agreement. Start with scope. Tucker (2003, 509-510) argues that a 1 In philosophy of science until the early 1980s, scientific consensus was addressed mostly in the context of Kuhn’s (1962/1970) The Structure of the Scientific Revolutions (See Wray in this volume). For a classic account of the interplay between data, theory, method, and rational consensus, see Laudan (1984).
共识与异议的社会认识论
本文回顾了当前社会认识论中关于知识与共识关系的争论。这些关系本身在哲学上很有趣,但也有实际后果,因为共识在为公共决策提供信息方面发挥着越来越重要的作用。本文探讨了以下问题。什么时候共识可以归因于一个认知共同体?在什么条件下,我们可以合理地推断出共识观点是基于知识的,或者是在认识论上被证明的?共识应该是科学探究的目标吗?如果是,什么样的共识?如何处理异议?有人认为,一个理论是正确的,从有一个科学共识这一事实的合法推论需要考虑到理论的认知属性以及共识的社会属性。论文的最后一部分回顾了共识形成的计算模型。共识在公共生活中发挥着越来越大的作用。美国国立卫生研究院(NIH)和政府间气候变化专门委员会(IPCC)制定专家共识声明,为有争议的问题提供权威答案。“丹麦公民共识模型”用于评估科学和技术的社会维度(Medlock等人,2007;霍斯特2008;einsedel et al. 2001)。维基百科促进共识,以实现中立性和可验证性(维基百科2017)。在法律审判中,在相互对立的专家之间进行仲裁时,要遵循科学共识。但当我们思考知识和共识之间的关系时,就会产生两种相互冲突的直觉。一方面,从什么时候开始,事实是由数字决定的?我们是不是又回到了1897年臭名昭著的印第安纳州众议院“圆周率法案”,该法案通过多数投票重新定义了圆周率?(Hallerberg, 1977)虽然伽利略的观点与常识相悖,但他不是正确的吗?另一方面,每有一个伽利略,就有数百个被历史所遗忘的误入歧途的反对者。是不是每个人都错了,只有你是对的?当前的共识和异议的社会认识论整理了这些相互冲突的直觉。社会认识论区分基于知识的共识和单纯的协议,探索共识和探究目标之间的关系,区分合法的和非法的异议。第1节关注共识归属于认知共同体。第2节回顾了基于知识的或认识论上合理的共识。第3节讨论了作为调查目的的共识和异议的规范地位。第4节回顾了共识的计算模型。1. 什么时候存在共识?决定是否存在共识并不总是微不足道的。为此,我们需要评估协议的范围和深度。从范围开始。塔克(2003,509-510)认为,在20世纪80年代早期的科学哲学中,科学共识主要是在库恩(1962/1970)的《科学革命的结构》(见本卷中的Wray)的背景下解决的。有关数据、理论、方法和理性共识之间相互作用的经典描述,请参见劳丹(1984)。
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
求助全文
约1分钟内获得全文 求助全文
来源期刊
自引率
0.00%
发文量
0
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
确定
请完成安全验证×
copy
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
右上角分享
点击右上角分享
0
联系我们:info@booksci.cn Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。 Copyright © 2023 布克学术 All rights reserved.
京ICP备2023020795号-1
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术官方微信