{"title":"Traumatic Hermeneutics: Reading and Overreading the Pain of Others","authors":"C. Davis","doi":"10.5250/STORYWORLDS.8.1.0031","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"How can I know that someone else is in pain, let alone have any real knowledge of what that pain feels like? Considering these questions, Wittgenstein answers them with breathtaking directness. Neither dismissing nor solving the problem, he tells us all we can know and all we need to know: “If I see someone writhing in pain with evident cause I do not think: all the same, his feelings are hidden from me” (1958: 223). I can doubt most things if I put my mind to it; and of course I cannot know precisely how another’s pain feels. But if I see a person who has been hit by a truck, it would be better to call for help than to consider the merits of philosophical scepticism. As Wittgenstein puts it in another passage, “Just try – in a real case – to doubt someone else’s fear or pain” (1958: 102). We cannot directly share it, but we know it when we see it. The case of trauma and of trauma texts nevertheless complicates the recognition of the other’s pain. Wittgenstein refers to suffering which is visible (“I see someone writhing in pain”) and has “evident cause.” Its source and its signs cannot be misinterpreted: the truck hit a person who is now crying in agony. The causes and symptoms of trauma, however, are less obviously manifest and more easily mistakable. This is suggested in one of the most frequently quoted passages in trauma studies, where Freud describes the survivor of a train crash in Moses and Monotheism:","PeriodicalId":424412,"journal":{"name":"Storyworlds: A Journal of Narrative Studies","volume":"8 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0000,"publicationDate":"2016-09-09","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":"1","resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"Storyworlds: A Journal of Narrative Studies","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.5250/STORYWORLDS.8.1.0031","RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":null,"ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"","JCRName":"","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
Abstract
How can I know that someone else is in pain, let alone have any real knowledge of what that pain feels like? Considering these questions, Wittgenstein answers them with breathtaking directness. Neither dismissing nor solving the problem, he tells us all we can know and all we need to know: “If I see someone writhing in pain with evident cause I do not think: all the same, his feelings are hidden from me” (1958: 223). I can doubt most things if I put my mind to it; and of course I cannot know precisely how another’s pain feels. But if I see a person who has been hit by a truck, it would be better to call for help than to consider the merits of philosophical scepticism. As Wittgenstein puts it in another passage, “Just try – in a real case – to doubt someone else’s fear or pain” (1958: 102). We cannot directly share it, but we know it when we see it. The case of trauma and of trauma texts nevertheless complicates the recognition of the other’s pain. Wittgenstein refers to suffering which is visible (“I see someone writhing in pain”) and has “evident cause.” Its source and its signs cannot be misinterpreted: the truck hit a person who is now crying in agony. The causes and symptoms of trauma, however, are less obviously manifest and more easily mistakable. This is suggested in one of the most frequently quoted passages in trauma studies, where Freud describes the survivor of a train crash in Moses and Monotheism: