Generic interpretations of possessive recursion in English-speaking children

Tyler Poisson, J. de Villiers, Hirsto Kyuchukov, Bea Weinand, Lillian Young, Sofia Morales, Laisha Aniceto
{"title":"Generic interpretations of possessive recursion in English-speaking children","authors":"Tyler Poisson, J. de Villiers, Hirsto Kyuchukov, Bea Weinand, Lillian Young, Sofia Morales, Laisha Aniceto","doi":"10.3765/plsa.v8i1.5496","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"Two-part s-possessives such as the dad’s kid’s bike admit at least two distinct interpretations: the dad has a kid who has a bike, or the dad has a bike that is made for kids. We propose that the former interpretation derives from recursively embedding DP-possessives, and the latter from representing kid’s bike as a generic NP-possessive. Accordingly, in the right context, two-part s-possessives are fully ambiguous for adults between ‘recursive’ and ‘generic’ readings. These readings can be disambiguated syntactically. Consider the difference in meaning when we insert a relative clause and extract the constituent kid’s bike — the kid’s bike that is the dad’s — versus when we extract the head noun bike — the bike that is the dad’s kid’s. Our story-based experiment demonstrates that 4-7-year-olds (N=79) and adults (N=68) strongly favor (~80%) the generic interpretation of phrases like the kid’s bike that is the dad’s, as the A-over-A constraint blocks the extraction of a DP-possessive out of a recursive DP. Similarly, adults show a strong preference (~80%) for recursive interpretations of phrases like the bike that is the dad’s kid’s, as the A-over-A constraint blocks the extraction of the head noun bike out of the generic NP-possessive kid’s bike. However, 4-5-year-olds admit generic readings of these recursive phrases 54% of the time; it is not until 6 or 7 years that children show an adult-like preference for the recursive interpretation (~80%). These data support two complementary claims. First, that recursive possessives are acquired late on account of their syntax, and second that children, like adults, represent generic possessives under a different syntactic node than regular possessives.","PeriodicalId":299752,"journal":{"name":"Proceedings of the Linguistic Society of America","volume":"1 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0000,"publicationDate":"2023-04-27","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":"0","resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"Proceedings of the Linguistic Society of America","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.3765/plsa.v8i1.5496","RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":null,"ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"","JCRName":"","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0

Abstract

Two-part s-possessives such as the dad’s kid’s bike admit at least two distinct interpretations: the dad has a kid who has a bike, or the dad has a bike that is made for kids. We propose that the former interpretation derives from recursively embedding DP-possessives, and the latter from representing kid’s bike as a generic NP-possessive. Accordingly, in the right context, two-part s-possessives are fully ambiguous for adults between ‘recursive’ and ‘generic’ readings. These readings can be disambiguated syntactically. Consider the difference in meaning when we insert a relative clause and extract the constituent kid’s bike — the kid’s bike that is the dad’s — versus when we extract the head noun bike — the bike that is the dad’s kid’s. Our story-based experiment demonstrates that 4-7-year-olds (N=79) and adults (N=68) strongly favor (~80%) the generic interpretation of phrases like the kid’s bike that is the dad’s, as the A-over-A constraint blocks the extraction of a DP-possessive out of a recursive DP. Similarly, adults show a strong preference (~80%) for recursive interpretations of phrases like the bike that is the dad’s kid’s, as the A-over-A constraint blocks the extraction of the head noun bike out of the generic NP-possessive kid’s bike. However, 4-5-year-olds admit generic readings of these recursive phrases 54% of the time; it is not until 6 or 7 years that children show an adult-like preference for the recursive interpretation (~80%). These data support two complementary claims. First, that recursive possessives are acquired late on account of their syntax, and second that children, like adults, represent generic possessives under a different syntactic node than regular possessives.
英语儿童所有格递归的一般解释
像“爸爸的孩子的自行车”这样的两部分s所有格至少有两种不同的解释:爸爸的孩子有一辆自行车,或者爸爸有一辆为孩子们制造的自行车。我们提出前一种解释来自递归嵌入dp所有格,后一种解释来自将儿童自行车表示为一般np所有格。因此,在正确的语境中,对于成年人来说,两部分s所有格在“递归”和“一般”阅读之间是完全模糊的。这些读数可以在语法上消除歧义。考虑一下当我们插入一个关系从句并提取组成部分kid 's bike(孩子的自行车是爸爸的)和提取词头名词bike(自行车是爸爸的孩子的)在意思上的区别。我们基于故事的实验表明,4-7岁的儿童(N=79)和成人(N=68)强烈支持(~80%)对短语的一般解释,如孩子的自行车是爸爸的,因为a -over- a约束阻碍了从递归DP中提取DP所有格。同样地,成年人也表现出强烈的偏好(约80%),倾向于递归解释像the bike that is the dad’s kid’s这样的短语,因为a -over- a约束阻碍了从一般的np所有格kid’s bike中提取首名词bike。然而,4-5岁的孩子在54%的时间里承认对这些递归短语有一般性的阅读;直到6、7岁,儿童才表现出对递归解释的成人偏好(约80%)。这些数据支持两个互补的说法。首先,递归所有格由于其语法而获得较晚,其次,儿童和成人一样,在不同的句法节点下代表一般所有格而不是规则所有格。
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
求助全文
约1分钟内获得全文 求助全文
来源期刊
自引率
0.00%
发文量
0
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
确定
请完成安全验证×
copy
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
右上角分享
点击右上角分享
0
联系我们:info@booksci.cn Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。 Copyright © 2023 布克学术 All rights reserved.
京ICP备2023020795号-1
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术官方微信