Neo-Roman Liberty in the Philosophy of Human Rights

Lena Halldenius
{"title":"Neo-Roman Liberty in the Philosophy of Human Rights","authors":"Lena Halldenius","doi":"10.1017/9781108951722.015","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"It is my contention here that Quentin Skinner’s conception of neo-roman liberty as it is articulated in Liberty Before Liberalism serves to establish two normative premises for human rights philosophy. Those premises are, first, that human rights should offer the strongest protection for those persons who are most vulnerable and liable to social and political discrimination and marginalisation. Second, the objects of human rights should be conceptualised in terms of open-ended goals of justice, predicated on a commitment to structural equality. I will have reason to refer to a reflection that Skinner makes on utopianism and how the “classic liberal case” of liberty can be associated with a critique of utopianism in political theory. By utopianism Skinner means – with reference to William Paley – a political theory that incorporates into its concepts demands that cannot be met without a fundamental change of practice and which moves beyond what it is at present reasonable for most people to expect of life. On this understanding, Skinner points out, John Rawls’s A Theory of Justice is a utopian treatise: it does not adapt to whatever is politically feasible but sets a challenging standard of justice for political institutions. I would qualify this by saying that the challenging nature of Rawls’s theory of justice is connected to the fact that it is systemic rather than utopian. A fear of the charge of utopianism is one of the recurrent features of human rights philosophy as we know it today. This is manifest in an incongruous tendency to join a moral philosophy of the good life with a political theory of basic provisions and life at the subsistence level. I hope to show that there is a consistent neo-roman case to be made for a more politically challenging human rights philosophy. (Less)","PeriodicalId":147072,"journal":{"name":"Rethinking Liberty before Liberalism","volume":"1 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0000,"publicationDate":"2022-02-03","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":"0","resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"Rethinking Liberty before Liberalism","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108951722.015","RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":null,"ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"","JCRName":"","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0

Abstract

It is my contention here that Quentin Skinner’s conception of neo-roman liberty as it is articulated in Liberty Before Liberalism serves to establish two normative premises for human rights philosophy. Those premises are, first, that human rights should offer the strongest protection for those persons who are most vulnerable and liable to social and political discrimination and marginalisation. Second, the objects of human rights should be conceptualised in terms of open-ended goals of justice, predicated on a commitment to structural equality. I will have reason to refer to a reflection that Skinner makes on utopianism and how the “classic liberal case” of liberty can be associated with a critique of utopianism in political theory. By utopianism Skinner means – with reference to William Paley – a political theory that incorporates into its concepts demands that cannot be met without a fundamental change of practice and which moves beyond what it is at present reasonable for most people to expect of life. On this understanding, Skinner points out, John Rawls’s A Theory of Justice is a utopian treatise: it does not adapt to whatever is politically feasible but sets a challenging standard of justice for political institutions. I would qualify this by saying that the challenging nature of Rawls’s theory of justice is connected to the fact that it is systemic rather than utopian. A fear of the charge of utopianism is one of the recurrent features of human rights philosophy as we know it today. This is manifest in an incongruous tendency to join a moral philosophy of the good life with a political theory of basic provisions and life at the subsistence level. I hope to show that there is a consistent neo-roman case to be made for a more politically challenging human rights philosophy. (Less)
人权哲学中的新罗马自由
我的观点是,昆汀·斯金纳在《先于自由主义的自由》一书中所阐述的新罗马自由概念为人权哲学建立了两个规范性前提。这些前提是,第一,人权应该为那些最脆弱和最容易受到社会和政治歧视和边缘化的人提供最强有力的保护。第二,人权的目标应以对结构平等的承诺为基础,根据开放性的正义目标加以概念化。我将有理由提到斯金纳对乌托邦主义的反思,以及自由的“经典自由主义案例”如何与政治理论中对乌托邦主义的批判联系在一起。谈及乌托邦主义,斯金纳指的是——参照威廉·佩利——一种政治理论,它将一些要求融入到它的概念中,而这些要求只有在实践发生根本改变的情况下才能得到满足,并且超越了目前大多数人对生活的合理期望。在这种理解下,斯金纳指出,约翰·罗尔斯的《正义论》是一篇乌托邦式的论文:它不适应任何政治上可行的东西,而是为政治制度设定了一个具有挑战性的正义标准。我想说的是,罗尔斯正义理论的挑战本质与它是系统的而不是乌托邦的这一事实有关。害怕被指责为乌托邦主义是我们今天所知的人权哲学反复出现的特征之一。这表现在一种不协调的倾向,即把美好生活的道德哲学与基本供给和维持生计的生活的政治理论结合起来。我希望表明,有一个一致的新罗马案例,可以为一种更具政治挑战性的人权哲学提供支持。(少)
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
求助全文
约1分钟内获得全文 求助全文
来源期刊
自引率
0.00%
发文量
0
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
确定
请完成安全验证×
copy
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
右上角分享
点击右上角分享
0
联系我们:info@booksci.cn Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。 Copyright © 2023 布克学术 All rights reserved.
京ICP备2023020795号-1
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:604180095
Book学术官方微信