{"title":"Science in the Scottish Enlightenment","authors":"P. Wood","doi":"10.1017/CCOL0521802733.006","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"During the past thirty years the role of the natural sciences and medicine in the Scottish Enlightenment has been hotly debated. Elaborating on the interpretation of the Scottish Enlightenment advanced by Nicholas Phillipson, John Christie argued in a series of influential essays that the pursuit of natural knowledge was one of the 'major elements whose combination formed the culture of the Scottish Enlightenment'. Stronger claims for the importance of science and medicine were subsequently made by Roger L. Emerson, who contended that if we are properly to understand the origins and defining characteristics of the Scottish Enlightenment then we must see the cultivation of natural knowledge as being central to enlightened culture in eighteenth-century Scotland. On the other hand, following the lead of Hugh Trevor-Roper (Lord Dacre), John Robertson recently insisted that the Scottish Enlightenment should be defined in terms of a core of related enquiries in moral philosophy, history and political economy, and that the natural sciences and medicine were peripheral to the intellectual preoccupations of enlightened savants in Scotland and in the Atlantic world more generally. Richard Sher likewise rejects Emerson's claims, and suggests that the Scottish Enlightenment can be more fruitfully defined in terms of the 'culture of the literati' which, for Sher, encompassed science and medicine but was not rooted in these fields. While it would be inappropriate here to enter into the complexities of this debate, we should recognise that the points at issue are far from trivial because they raise serious questions not only about how we characterise the Enlightenment as an historical phenomenon but also about how we conceptualise the genesis of our own world.","PeriodicalId":234905,"journal":{"name":"The Cambridge Companion to the Scottish Enlightenment","volume":"10 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0000,"publicationDate":"2003-04-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":"6","resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"The Cambridge Companion to the Scottish Enlightenment","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.1017/CCOL0521802733.006","RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":null,"ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"","JCRName":"","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 6
Abstract
During the past thirty years the role of the natural sciences and medicine in the Scottish Enlightenment has been hotly debated. Elaborating on the interpretation of the Scottish Enlightenment advanced by Nicholas Phillipson, John Christie argued in a series of influential essays that the pursuit of natural knowledge was one of the 'major elements whose combination formed the culture of the Scottish Enlightenment'. Stronger claims for the importance of science and medicine were subsequently made by Roger L. Emerson, who contended that if we are properly to understand the origins and defining characteristics of the Scottish Enlightenment then we must see the cultivation of natural knowledge as being central to enlightened culture in eighteenth-century Scotland. On the other hand, following the lead of Hugh Trevor-Roper (Lord Dacre), John Robertson recently insisted that the Scottish Enlightenment should be defined in terms of a core of related enquiries in moral philosophy, history and political economy, and that the natural sciences and medicine were peripheral to the intellectual preoccupations of enlightened savants in Scotland and in the Atlantic world more generally. Richard Sher likewise rejects Emerson's claims, and suggests that the Scottish Enlightenment can be more fruitfully defined in terms of the 'culture of the literati' which, for Sher, encompassed science and medicine but was not rooted in these fields. While it would be inappropriate here to enter into the complexities of this debate, we should recognise that the points at issue are far from trivial because they raise serious questions not only about how we characterise the Enlightenment as an historical phenomenon but also about how we conceptualise the genesis of our own world.
在过去的三十年中,自然科学和医学在苏格兰启蒙运动中的作用一直备受争议。约翰·克里斯蒂在阐述尼古拉斯·菲利普森提出的对苏格兰启蒙运动的解释时,在一系列有影响力的文章中指出,对自然知识的追求是“形成苏格兰启蒙文化的主要因素之一”。罗杰·l·爱默生(Roger L. Emerson)随后对科学和医学的重要性提出了更有力的主张,他认为,如果我们要正确理解苏格兰启蒙运动的起源和定义特征,那么我们必须将自然知识的培养视为18世纪苏格兰启蒙文化的核心。另一方面,在休·特雷弗-罗珀(戴克勋爵)的带领下,约翰·罗伯逊最近坚持认为,苏格兰启蒙运动应该被定义为道德哲学、历史和政治经济学等相关研究的核心,而自然科学和医学在苏格兰和大西洋世界的开明学者的智力关注中处于边缘地位。理查德·谢尔同样反对爱默生的说法,他认为苏格兰启蒙运动可以用“文人文化”来定义,对谢尔来说,“文人文化”包含了科学和医学,但并不根植于这些领域。虽然在这里进入这场辩论的复杂性是不合适的,但我们应该认识到,争论的要点远非微不足道,因为它们不仅提出了我们如何将启蒙运动定性为一种历史现象的严肃问题,而且还提出了我们如何概念化我们自己世界的起源的严肃问题。