Notes Toward an Understanding of Freedom of Conscience

S. Murphy
{"title":"Notes Toward an Understanding of Freedom of Conscience","authors":"S. Murphy","doi":"10.2139/SSRN.2025268","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"Commentators wrestling with conflicts between claims of conscience made by health care workers and demands for morally controversial services have offered a variety of responses. Despite these efforts, controversy about freedom of conscience in health care continues. It subsides from time to time, only to erupt again with renewed force when tectonic political and social forces collide. Discussion has not gone deep enough to address underlying disagreements about the nature of the human person that shape disputes about freedom of conscience. Proposals to limit freedom of conscience must first take into account the distinction between its perfective and preservative forms. Limiting perfective freedom of conscience prevents people from doing the good that they wish to do, and may (if no alternatives are available) prevent them from perfecting themselves, fulfilling their personal aspirations or achieving some social goals. This may do them some wrong. But if it does them some wrong, it does not necessarily do them an injury. In contrast, to force people to do something they believe to be wrong is always an assault on their personal dignity and essential humanity, even if they are objectively in error; it is always harmful to the individual, and it always has negative implications for society. This does not mean that no limit can ever be placed on preservative freedom of conscience. It does mean, however, that even the strict approach taken to limiting other fundamental rights and freedoms is not sufficiently refined to be safely applied to limit freedom of conscience in its preservative form. The stakes are far too high. Like the use of potentially deadly force, if the restriction of preservative freedom of conscience can be justified at all, it will only be as a last resort, and only in the most exceptional circumstances.","PeriodicalId":444809,"journal":{"name":"Risk Factors in Asset Returns","volume":"37 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0000,"publicationDate":"2012-03-15","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":"2","resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"Risk Factors in Asset Returns","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.2139/SSRN.2025268","RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":null,"ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"","JCRName":"","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 2

Abstract

Commentators wrestling with conflicts between claims of conscience made by health care workers and demands for morally controversial services have offered a variety of responses. Despite these efforts, controversy about freedom of conscience in health care continues. It subsides from time to time, only to erupt again with renewed force when tectonic political and social forces collide. Discussion has not gone deep enough to address underlying disagreements about the nature of the human person that shape disputes about freedom of conscience. Proposals to limit freedom of conscience must first take into account the distinction between its perfective and preservative forms. Limiting perfective freedom of conscience prevents people from doing the good that they wish to do, and may (if no alternatives are available) prevent them from perfecting themselves, fulfilling their personal aspirations or achieving some social goals. This may do them some wrong. But if it does them some wrong, it does not necessarily do them an injury. In contrast, to force people to do something they believe to be wrong is always an assault on their personal dignity and essential humanity, even if they are objectively in error; it is always harmful to the individual, and it always has negative implications for society. This does not mean that no limit can ever be placed on preservative freedom of conscience. It does mean, however, that even the strict approach taken to limiting other fundamental rights and freedoms is not sufficiently refined to be safely applied to limit freedom of conscience in its preservative form. The stakes are far too high. Like the use of potentially deadly force, if the restriction of preservative freedom of conscience can be justified at all, it will only be as a last resort, and only in the most exceptional circumstances.
对良心自由的理解
在卫生保健工作者提出的良心要求与道德上有争议的服务需求之间的冲突中,评论员们给出了各种各样的回应。尽管做出了这些努力,但关于医疗保健中良心自由的争议仍在继续。它不时地消退,只有当结构性政治和社会力量发生冲突时,它才会再次迸发出新的力量。讨论还没有深入到足以解决关于人的本质的潜在分歧,这些分歧形成了关于良心自由的争论。限制良心自由的建议必须首先考虑到其完美形式和保留形式之间的区别。限制完全的良心自由会阻碍人们做他们想做的好事,而且(如果没有其他选择的话)可能会阻碍他们完善自己,实现他们的个人愿望或实现一些社会目标。这可能会给他们带来一些错误。但如果它做错了,它不一定会伤害他们。相反,强迫人们做他们认为是错误的事情,总是对他们个人尊严和基本人性的侵犯,即使他们客观上是错误的;它对个人总是有害的,对社会总是有负面影响。这并不意味着不可以对保守的良心自由加以限制。然而,它确实意味着,即使采取严格的方法来限制其他基本权利和自由,也不足以完善到可以安全地用于限制保存形式的良心自由。赌注太高了。就像使用可能致命的武力一样,如果限制保护性的良心自由是正当的,那也只能作为最后的手段,而且只能在最特殊的情况下使用。
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
求助全文
约1分钟内获得全文 求助全文
来源期刊
自引率
0.00%
发文量
0
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
确定
请完成安全验证×
copy
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
右上角分享
点击右上角分享
0
联系我们:info@booksci.cn Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。 Copyright © 2023 布克学术 All rights reserved.
京ICP备2023020795号-1
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术官方微信