Lotteries for Shared Experiences

N. Arnosti, Carlos Bonet
{"title":"Lotteries for Shared Experiences","authors":"N. Arnosti, Carlos Bonet","doi":"10.1145/3490486.3538312","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"We consider a model with k identical tickets. The set of agents (N) is partitioned into a set of groups, and agents have dichotomous preferences: an agent is successful if and only if members of her group receive enough tickets for everyone in the group. We treat the group structure as private information, unknown to the designer. Because there are only k tickets, there can be at most k successful agents. We define the efficiency of a lottery allocation to be the expected number of successful agents, divided by k. If this is at least β, then the allocation is β-efficient. A lottery allocation is fair if each agent has the same success probability, and β-fair if for any pair of agents, the ratio of their success probabilities is at least β. Given these definitions, we seek lottery allocations that are both approximately efficient and approximately fair. Although this may be unattainable if groups are large, in many cases group sizes are much smaller than the total number of tickets. We define a family of instances characterized by two parameters, κ and α. The parameter κ bounds the ratio of group size to total number of tickets, while α bounds the supply-demand ratio. For any κ and α, we provide worst-case performance guarantees in terms of efficiency and fairness. We first consider a scenario where applicants can identify each member of their group. Here, the mechanism typically used is the Group Lottery, which orders groups uniformly at random and processes them sequentially. We show that this mechanism incentivizes agents to truthfully report their groups. Moreover, we prove that the Group Lottery is (1 - κ)-efficient and (1-2κ)-fair. It is not perfectly efficient, as tickets might be wasted if the size of the group being processed exceeds the number of remaining tickets. It is not perfectly fair, since once only a few tickets remain, a large group can no longer be successful, but a small group can. Furthermore, we show that these guarantees are tight. Could there be a mechanism with stronger performance guarantees than the Group Lottery? We answer this question by establishing the limits of what can be achieved. Specifically, there always exists an allocation (π) that is (1-κ)-efficient and fair, but for any ε > 0, there are examples where any allocation that is (1- κ + ε)-efficient is not even ε-fair. To show the existence of the random allocation (π), we use a generalization of the Birkhoff-von Neumann theorem proved by [1]. By awarding groups according to the allocation (π), we can obtain a mechanism that attains the best possible performance guarantees. Therefore, the 2 κ loss in fairness in the Group Lottery can be thought of as the \"cost\" of using a simple procedure that orders groups uniformly, rather than employing a Birkhoff-von Neumann decomposition to generate the allocation (π). In many applications, developing an interface that allows applicants to list their group members may be too cumbersome. This motivates the study of a second scenario, where applicants are only allowed to specify the number of tickets they need. The natural mechanism in this setting is the Individual Lottery. Unfortunately, we show that the Individual Lottery may lead to arbitrarily inefficient and unfair outcomes. It is perhaps not surprising that the Individual Lottery will be inefficient if agents request more tickets than needed, or if each agent has a large chance of success. However, we show that the waste due to over-allocation may be severe even if all agents request only their group size and demand far exceeds supply. Furthermore, because the probability of success will be roughly proportional to group size, small groups are at a significant disadvantage. Can we achieve approximate efficiency and fairness without asking applicants to identify each member of their group? We show that this is possible with a minor modification to the Individual Lottery which gives applicants with larger requests a lower chance of being allocated. This eliminates the incentive to inflate demand, and reduces the possibility of multiple winners from the same group. To make the allocation fair, we choose a particular method for biasing the lottery against large requests: sequentially select individuals with probability inversely proportional to their request. We call this approach the Weighted Individual Lottery. In the Weighted Individual Lottery, a group of four individuals who each request four tickets has the same chance of being drawn next as a group of two individuals who each request two tickets. As a result, outcomes are similar to the Group Lottery. We prove that the Weighted Individual Lottery is (1-κ-α/2)-efficient and (1-2κ-α/2)-fair (in fact, we provide slightly stronger guarantees). Notice that these guarantees coincide with those of the Group Lottery when demand far exceeds supply (α is close to 0). Our main results are summarized in Table 1. Our conclusion is that the Individual Lottery can be arbitrarily unfair and inefficient. These deficiencies can be mostly eliminated by using a Group Lottery. Perhaps more surprisingly, approximate efficiency and fairness can also be achieved while maintaining the Individual Lottery interface, by suitably biasing the lottery against agents with large requests.","PeriodicalId":209859,"journal":{"name":"Proceedings of the 23rd ACM Conference on Economics and Computation","volume":null,"pages":null},"PeriodicalIF":0.0000,"publicationDate":"2022-05-22","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":"1","resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"Proceedings of the 23rd ACM Conference on Economics and Computation","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.1145/3490486.3538312","RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":null,"ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"","JCRName":"","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1

Abstract

We consider a model with k identical tickets. The set of agents (N) is partitioned into a set of groups, and agents have dichotomous preferences: an agent is successful if and only if members of her group receive enough tickets for everyone in the group. We treat the group structure as private information, unknown to the designer. Because there are only k tickets, there can be at most k successful agents. We define the efficiency of a lottery allocation to be the expected number of successful agents, divided by k. If this is at least β, then the allocation is β-efficient. A lottery allocation is fair if each agent has the same success probability, and β-fair if for any pair of agents, the ratio of their success probabilities is at least β. Given these definitions, we seek lottery allocations that are both approximately efficient and approximately fair. Although this may be unattainable if groups are large, in many cases group sizes are much smaller than the total number of tickets. We define a family of instances characterized by two parameters, κ and α. The parameter κ bounds the ratio of group size to total number of tickets, while α bounds the supply-demand ratio. For any κ and α, we provide worst-case performance guarantees in terms of efficiency and fairness. We first consider a scenario where applicants can identify each member of their group. Here, the mechanism typically used is the Group Lottery, which orders groups uniformly at random and processes them sequentially. We show that this mechanism incentivizes agents to truthfully report their groups. Moreover, we prove that the Group Lottery is (1 - κ)-efficient and (1-2κ)-fair. It is not perfectly efficient, as tickets might be wasted if the size of the group being processed exceeds the number of remaining tickets. It is not perfectly fair, since once only a few tickets remain, a large group can no longer be successful, but a small group can. Furthermore, we show that these guarantees are tight. Could there be a mechanism with stronger performance guarantees than the Group Lottery? We answer this question by establishing the limits of what can be achieved. Specifically, there always exists an allocation (π) that is (1-κ)-efficient and fair, but for any ε > 0, there are examples where any allocation that is (1- κ + ε)-efficient is not even ε-fair. To show the existence of the random allocation (π), we use a generalization of the Birkhoff-von Neumann theorem proved by [1]. By awarding groups according to the allocation (π), we can obtain a mechanism that attains the best possible performance guarantees. Therefore, the 2 κ loss in fairness in the Group Lottery can be thought of as the "cost" of using a simple procedure that orders groups uniformly, rather than employing a Birkhoff-von Neumann decomposition to generate the allocation (π). In many applications, developing an interface that allows applicants to list their group members may be too cumbersome. This motivates the study of a second scenario, where applicants are only allowed to specify the number of tickets they need. The natural mechanism in this setting is the Individual Lottery. Unfortunately, we show that the Individual Lottery may lead to arbitrarily inefficient and unfair outcomes. It is perhaps not surprising that the Individual Lottery will be inefficient if agents request more tickets than needed, or if each agent has a large chance of success. However, we show that the waste due to over-allocation may be severe even if all agents request only their group size and demand far exceeds supply. Furthermore, because the probability of success will be roughly proportional to group size, small groups are at a significant disadvantage. Can we achieve approximate efficiency and fairness without asking applicants to identify each member of their group? We show that this is possible with a minor modification to the Individual Lottery which gives applicants with larger requests a lower chance of being allocated. This eliminates the incentive to inflate demand, and reduces the possibility of multiple winners from the same group. To make the allocation fair, we choose a particular method for biasing the lottery against large requests: sequentially select individuals with probability inversely proportional to their request. We call this approach the Weighted Individual Lottery. In the Weighted Individual Lottery, a group of four individuals who each request four tickets has the same chance of being drawn next as a group of two individuals who each request two tickets. As a result, outcomes are similar to the Group Lottery. We prove that the Weighted Individual Lottery is (1-κ-α/2)-efficient and (1-2κ-α/2)-fair (in fact, we provide slightly stronger guarantees). Notice that these guarantees coincide with those of the Group Lottery when demand far exceeds supply (α is close to 0). Our main results are summarized in Table 1. Our conclusion is that the Individual Lottery can be arbitrarily unfair and inefficient. These deficiencies can be mostly eliminated by using a Group Lottery. Perhaps more surprisingly, approximate efficiency and fairness can also be achieved while maintaining the Individual Lottery interface, by suitably biasing the lottery against agents with large requests.
分享经验的彩票
我们考虑一个有k张相同门票的模型。代理的集合(N)被划分为一组,并且代理具有二分类偏好:当且仅当她所在组的成员获得足够的票时,代理是成功的。我们将组结构视为设计者不知道的私有信息。因为只有k张票,所以最多只能有k个成功的代理人。我们将彩票分配的效率定义为成功代理的期望数量除以k。如果这至少是β,那么分配是β-有效的。如果每个代理都有相同的成功概率,那么抽签分配是公平的,如果对于任何一对代理,他们的成功概率之比至少为β,那么抽签分配是公平的。鉴于这些定义,我们寻求彩票分配既近似有效又近似公平。虽然如果团体很大,这可能是不可能实现的,但在许多情况下,团体人数远小于门票总数。我们定义了一个由两个参数κ和α表征的实例族。参数κ限定了群体规模与总票数的比值,而α限定了供需比。对于任何κ和α,我们在效率和公平性方面提供了最坏情况下的性能保证。我们首先考虑这样一个场景:申请人可以识别他们组中的每个成员。这里,通常使用的机制是Group Lottery,它对组进行统一随机排序,并按顺序处理它们。我们表明,这种机制激励代理人如实报告他们的群体。此外,我们还证明了群体彩票是(1- κ)高效和(1-2κ)公平的。它不是完全有效的,因为如果正在处理的组的规模超过剩余的票数量,可能会浪费票。这不是完全公平的,因为一旦只剩下几张票,一大群人就不能再成功了,但一小群人可以。此外,我们表明这些保证是严格的。是否有一种机制比团体彩票更能保证业绩?我们通过确定所能达到的限度来回答这个问题。具体地说,总是存在一个分配(π)是(1-κ)有效和公平的,但对于任何ε > 0,存在任何分配(1-κ + ε)有效甚至不是ε公平的例子。为了证明随机分配π的存在性,我们使用了由[1]证明的Birkhoff-von Neumann定理的推广。通过根据分配(π)对组进行奖励,我们可以获得一种实现最佳性能保证的机制。因此,在分组抽签中公平性的2 κ损失可以被认为是使用一个简单的过程来统一排序分组的“成本”,而不是使用Birkhoff-von Neumann分解来生成分配(π)。在许多应用程序中,开发允许申请人列出其组成员的界面可能过于繁琐。这激发了对第二种情况的研究,在这种情况下,申请人只被允许指定他们需要的门票数量。这种情况下的自然机制就是个人彩票。不幸的是,我们表明个人彩票可能导致任意低效和不公平的结果。如果代理请求的票多于所需的票,或者每个代理都有很大的成功机会,那么个人彩票将是低效的,这也许并不令人惊讶。然而,我们表明,即使所有的代理只要求他们的群体规模,需求远远超过供应,由于过度分配的浪费可能是严重的。此外,由于成功的概率大致与群体规模成正比,小团体处于明显的劣势。我们能在不要求申请人识别其组中的每个成员的情况下实现近似的效率和公平吗?我们表明,这是可能的,对个人彩票稍加修改,使申请人有较大的要求,分配的机会较低。这就消除了膨胀需求的动机,降低了同一群体中出现多个赢家的可能性。为了使分配公平,我们选择了一种特殊的方法来使彩票对大请求有偏见:顺序地选择概率与请求成反比的个体。我们称这种方法为加权个人彩票。在加权个人彩票中,一组四个人每人要求四张票,与一组两个人每人要求两张票的机会相同。因此,结果与团体彩票相似。我们证明了加权个人彩票是(1-κ-α/2)高效和(1-2κ-α/2)公平的(事实上,我们提供了稍强的保证)。请注意,当需求远远超过供应时,这些保证与团体彩票的保证一致(α接近于0)。我们的主要结果总结在表1中。 我们的结论是,个人彩票可能是任意不公平和低效的。这些缺陷大多可以通过使用集体抽签来消除。也许更令人惊讶的是,在维护个人彩票接口的同时,通过适当地使彩票对具有大请求的代理有偏倚,也可以实现近似的效率和公平性。
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
求助全文
约1分钟内获得全文 求助全文
来源期刊
自引率
0.00%
发文量
0
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
确定
请完成安全验证×
copy
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
右上角分享
点击右上角分享
0
联系我们:info@booksci.cn Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。 Copyright © 2023 布克学术 All rights reserved.
京ICP备2023020795号-1
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术官方微信