The Non-Aristotelian Novelty of Leibniz’s Teleology

Laurence Carlin
{"title":"The Non-Aristotelian Novelty of Leibniz’s Teleology","authors":"Laurence Carlin","doi":"10.5840/LEIBNIZ2011214","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"My aim in this paper is to underscore the novelty of Leibniz’s teleology from a historical perspective. I believe this perspective helps deliver a better understanding of the finer details of Leibniz’s employment of final causes. I argue in this paper that Leibniz was taking a stance on three central teleological issues that derive from Aristotle, issues that seem to have occupied nearly every advocate of final causes from Aristotle to Leibniz. I discuss the three Aristotelian issues, and how major thinkers treated them in the medieval period. I argue that Leibniz rejected all of the mainstream Aristotelian teleological views on these issues. I conclude that Leibniz broke with longstanding threads of teleological thinking in ways that were often extreme. L is famous for his attempts to rehabilitate certain Scholastic doctrines. It is well known, for example, that he incorporated substantial forms into his philosophy. His attempts to revive the doctrine of substantial forms have received a lot of attention in the scholarly literature. But the other major Aristotelian doctrine he sought to revive---the doctrine of final causes---has received far less attention until recently.1 Leibniz believed final causes were explanatorily relevant for every event at every ontological level of his system. And his commitment to the explanatory importance of efficient causes was equally firm. Any state of affairs in his system could be explained by way of efficient causation (at least, in principle). Moreover, each type of explanation is sufficient on its own for a complete explanation of any given state of affairs in Leibniz’s system. This implies, as Jeffrey McDonough has recently argued, that Leibniz had “a particularly novel, systematic, and intriguing picture of final-efficient explanatory overdetermination.”2 Any fact about the created world can be explained by appeal to a set of efficient causal laws, or a set of final causal laws, both of which govern the created world with equal explanatory power. I concur that Leibniz’s picture here is entirely novel, for careful attention to the historical record shows that Leibniz broke with longstanding threads of teleological thinking in ways that were often extreme. My aim in this paper is to underscore the novelty of Leibniz’s teleology from a historical perspective. This perspective helps, I think, not only to see the historical novelty of Leibniz’s teleology, but also","PeriodicalId":137959,"journal":{"name":"The Leibniz Review","volume":"23 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0000,"publicationDate":"2011-07-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":"3","resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"The Leibniz Review","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.5840/LEIBNIZ2011214","RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":null,"ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"","JCRName":"","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 3

Abstract

My aim in this paper is to underscore the novelty of Leibniz’s teleology from a historical perspective. I believe this perspective helps deliver a better understanding of the finer details of Leibniz’s employment of final causes. I argue in this paper that Leibniz was taking a stance on three central teleological issues that derive from Aristotle, issues that seem to have occupied nearly every advocate of final causes from Aristotle to Leibniz. I discuss the three Aristotelian issues, and how major thinkers treated them in the medieval period. I argue that Leibniz rejected all of the mainstream Aristotelian teleological views on these issues. I conclude that Leibniz broke with longstanding threads of teleological thinking in ways that were often extreme. L is famous for his attempts to rehabilitate certain Scholastic doctrines. It is well known, for example, that he incorporated substantial forms into his philosophy. His attempts to revive the doctrine of substantial forms have received a lot of attention in the scholarly literature. But the other major Aristotelian doctrine he sought to revive---the doctrine of final causes---has received far less attention until recently.1 Leibniz believed final causes were explanatorily relevant for every event at every ontological level of his system. And his commitment to the explanatory importance of efficient causes was equally firm. Any state of affairs in his system could be explained by way of efficient causation (at least, in principle). Moreover, each type of explanation is sufficient on its own for a complete explanation of any given state of affairs in Leibniz’s system. This implies, as Jeffrey McDonough has recently argued, that Leibniz had “a particularly novel, systematic, and intriguing picture of final-efficient explanatory overdetermination.”2 Any fact about the created world can be explained by appeal to a set of efficient causal laws, or a set of final causal laws, both of which govern the created world with equal explanatory power. I concur that Leibniz’s picture here is entirely novel, for careful attention to the historical record shows that Leibniz broke with longstanding threads of teleological thinking in ways that were often extreme. My aim in this paper is to underscore the novelty of Leibniz’s teleology from a historical perspective. This perspective helps, I think, not only to see the historical novelty of Leibniz’s teleology, but also
莱布尼茨目的论的非亚里士多德新颖性
本文的目的是从历史的角度来强调莱布尼茨目的论的新颖性。我相信这种观点有助于更好地理解莱布尼茨运用最终原因的细节。我在这篇论文中认为,莱布尼茨在三个中心目的论问题上的立场源自亚里士多德,这些问题似乎占据了从亚里士多德到莱布尼茨几乎每一个最终原因的倡导者。我将讨论亚里士多德的三个问题,以及中世纪主要思想家是如何对待它们的。我认为莱布尼茨在这些问题上拒绝了所有主流的亚里士多德目的论观点。我的结论是,莱布尼茨打破了长期以来的目的论思维,其方式往往是极端的。L以试图恢复某些经院学说而闻名。例如,众所周知,他将实体形式纳入他的哲学。他试图复兴实体形式学说的努力在学术文献中受到了广泛关注。但是,他试图复兴的另一个主要的亚里士多德学说——最终原因学说——直到最近才受到更少的关注莱布尼茨相信最终原因与他的系统的每一个本体论层面上的每一个事件都有解释关系。他对解释有效原因的重要性的承诺同样坚定。在他的体系中,任何事物的状态都可以用有效的因果关系来解释(至少在原则上)。此外,对于莱布尼茨体系中任何给定的事件状态,每种类型的解释本身都是充分的。正如杰弗里·麦克多诺(Jeffrey McDonough)最近所说,这意味着莱布尼茨“对最终有效的解释性过度决定有着特别新颖、系统和有趣的描述”。关于受造世界的任何事实都可以通过诉诸一套有效的因果律或一套最终的因果律来解释,这两种因果律都以同样的解释力支配着受造世界。我同意莱布尼茨在这里的描述完全是新颖的,因为对历史记录的仔细关注表明,莱布尼茨以极端的方式打破了长期以来的目的论思维线索。本文的目的是从历史的角度来强调莱布尼茨目的论的新颖性。我认为,这种观点不仅有助于我们看到莱布尼茨目的论的历史新颖性,而且
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
求助全文
约1分钟内获得全文 求助全文
来源期刊
CiteScore
0.10
自引率
0.00%
发文量
0
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
确定
请完成安全验证×
copy
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
右上角分享
点击右上角分享
0
联系我们:info@booksci.cn Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。 Copyright © 2023 布克学术 All rights reserved.
京ICP备2023020795号-1
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:604180095
Book学术官方微信