5. Private Selves and Public Lives: Neoclassical Perspectives

Inwardness
{"title":"5. Private Selves and Public Lives: Neoclassical Perspectives","authors":"Inwardness","doi":"10.1515/9783110691375-006","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"It is often claimed that modern concepts of individuality or the public sphere did not yet exist in the early modern period; or if they did, they looked and (probably) felt very different. There is a range of sociological and historical models and conceptual approaches to explain the emergence of a modern self-awareness of ‘individuals’ between 1300 and 1800 (see, for example, Greenblatt 1980; Taylor 1989; Mascuch 1996; Porter 1997). The problems begin with the word ‘individual’, which was not used in its modern meaning in the seventeenth century but may have “suggest[ed] a relation” rather than “a separate entity” (Stallybrass 1992, 606; see also Ferry 1983, 33–39). Similarly, the word ‘self’ was not used to denote the intrinsic, authentic, essential core of one human being (Ferry 1983, 39–45; Reiss 2003) and the word ‘subject’ did not mean an autonomous subject of decision and action but the subject as subditus, as subjected to the sovereign, sometimes contrasted to the ‘citizen’. Did the early moderns, then, not have a coherent and stable concept of selfhood or subjectivity? In contrast to this view, others emphasise “the conceptual importance of personal inwardness” (Maus 1995, 27; cf. Schoenfeldt 1999a, 11–13, 16–18). They focus on the textual traces of historically specific connections between concepts of privacy, inwardness, and personhood; they opt for a more pragmatic and limited analysis of the ways in which something like individuality becomes discernible in distinctions between inside and outside or between public and private spaces. From this vantage point, ‘subjectivity’ no longer appears as a (fairly) precise philosophical concept but as “a loose and varied collection of assumptions, intuitions, and practices that do not all logically entail one another and need not appear together at the same cultural moment” (Maus 1995, 29). That is to say that the imposition of a radical difference between modern and premodern forms of subjectivity (Barker 1984, Belsey 1985) can be as misguided as the assumption of continuity between them (Jagodzinski 1999b, 1–22). Continuities are almost inevitably evoked in conceptual histories that trace the semantic changes in words like ‘self’ and ‘individual’, too hastily assuming the existence of some entity to which the words are thought to refer. Conversely, the absence of a word in a certain period does not necessarily prove the non-existence of the concept in question. Inwardness, then, is less a concept than a cluster of “assumptions, intuitions, and practices” (Maus 1995, 29) which can be observed in different historical configurations. In this chapter, I present two case studies to explore how and why the distinction","PeriodicalId":122330,"journal":{"name":"Literary Culture in Early Modern England, 1630–1700","volume":"47 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0000,"publicationDate":"2020-06-22","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":"0","resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"Literary Culture in Early Modern England, 1630–1700","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.1515/9783110691375-006","RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":null,"ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"","JCRName":"","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0

Abstract

It is often claimed that modern concepts of individuality or the public sphere did not yet exist in the early modern period; or if they did, they looked and (probably) felt very different. There is a range of sociological and historical models and conceptual approaches to explain the emergence of a modern self-awareness of ‘individuals’ between 1300 and 1800 (see, for example, Greenblatt 1980; Taylor 1989; Mascuch 1996; Porter 1997). The problems begin with the word ‘individual’, which was not used in its modern meaning in the seventeenth century but may have “suggest[ed] a relation” rather than “a separate entity” (Stallybrass 1992, 606; see also Ferry 1983, 33–39). Similarly, the word ‘self’ was not used to denote the intrinsic, authentic, essential core of one human being (Ferry 1983, 39–45; Reiss 2003) and the word ‘subject’ did not mean an autonomous subject of decision and action but the subject as subditus, as subjected to the sovereign, sometimes contrasted to the ‘citizen’. Did the early moderns, then, not have a coherent and stable concept of selfhood or subjectivity? In contrast to this view, others emphasise “the conceptual importance of personal inwardness” (Maus 1995, 27; cf. Schoenfeldt 1999a, 11–13, 16–18). They focus on the textual traces of historically specific connections between concepts of privacy, inwardness, and personhood; they opt for a more pragmatic and limited analysis of the ways in which something like individuality becomes discernible in distinctions between inside and outside or between public and private spaces. From this vantage point, ‘subjectivity’ no longer appears as a (fairly) precise philosophical concept but as “a loose and varied collection of assumptions, intuitions, and practices that do not all logically entail one another and need not appear together at the same cultural moment” (Maus 1995, 29). That is to say that the imposition of a radical difference between modern and premodern forms of subjectivity (Barker 1984, Belsey 1985) can be as misguided as the assumption of continuity between them (Jagodzinski 1999b, 1–22). Continuities are almost inevitably evoked in conceptual histories that trace the semantic changes in words like ‘self’ and ‘individual’, too hastily assuming the existence of some entity to which the words are thought to refer. Conversely, the absence of a word in a certain period does not necessarily prove the non-existence of the concept in question. Inwardness, then, is less a concept than a cluster of “assumptions, intuitions, and practices” (Maus 1995, 29) which can be observed in different historical configurations. In this chapter, I present two case studies to explore how and why the distinction
5. 私人自我与公共生活:新古典主义观点
人们常常声称,个性或公共领域的现代概念在现代早期还不存在;或者,即使他们做了,他们看起来和(可能)感觉非常不同。有一系列社会学和历史模型和概念方法来解释1300年至1800年间“个人”的现代自我意识的出现(例如,参见Greenblatt 1980;泰勒1989年;Mascuch 1996;波特1997)。问题始于“个人”这个词,在17世纪,这个词的现代含义还没有被使用,但它可能“暗示了一种关系”,而不是“一个独立的实体”(Stallybrass 1992,606;另见Ferry 1983, 33-39)。同样,“自我”这个词也不被用来表示一个人内在的、真实的、基本的核心(Ferry 1983, 39-45;Reiss 2003),“主体”这个词并不是指决策和行动的自主主体,而是指臣服于主权者的主体,有时与“公民”形成对比。那么,早期的现代人就没有一个连贯而稳定的自我或主体性概念吗?与这种观点相反,其他人强调“个人内在性在概念上的重要性”(Maus 1995,27;参见Schoenfeldt 1999a, 11-13, 16-18)。他们关注隐私、内在性和人格等概念之间的历史特定联系的文本痕迹;他们选择了一种更务实和有限的分析方式,在这种方式中,像个性这样的东西在室内和室外或公共和私人空间之间的区别变得可辨。从这个有利的角度来看,“主体性”不再作为一个(相当)精确的哲学概念出现,而是作为“假设、直觉和实践的松散和多样化的集合,这些假设、直觉和实践在逻辑上并不都是相互关联的,也不需要在同一文化时刻一起出现”(Maus 1995,29)。也就是说,强加于现代和前现代主体性形式之间的根本差异(Barker 1984, Belsey 1985)可能与假设它们之间的连续性一样被误导(Jagodzinski 1999b, 1-22)。在追溯“自我”和“个人”等词的语义变化的概念历史中,连续性几乎不可避免地被唤起,过于匆忙地假设这些词被认为是指某些实体的存在。相反,一个词在某一时期的缺席并不一定证明这个概念的不存在。因此,内在性与其说是一个概念,不如说是一组“假设、直觉和实践”(Maus 1995,29),可以在不同的历史配置中观察到。在本章中,我提出了两个案例研究来探讨如何以及为什么这种区别
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
求助全文
约1分钟内获得全文 求助全文
来源期刊
自引率
0.00%
发文量
0
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
确定
请完成安全验证×
copy
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
右上角分享
点击右上角分享
0
联系我们:info@booksci.cn Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。 Copyright © 2023 布克学术 All rights reserved.
京ICP备2023020795号-1
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:604180095
Book学术官方微信