Leibnizian idealism

Craig Warmke
{"title":"Leibnizian idealism","authors":"Craig Warmke","doi":"10.4324/9781003202851-14","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"According to most interpreters, Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz (1646–1716) held a strong form of idealism according to which simple mental substances and their features exhaust fundamental reality. Leibniz called these substances monads (from the Greek word monas, ‘one’ or ‘unit’), and he assigns them two main features: (i) perceptual representations, and (ii) tendencies to move from one set of representations to the next. In more traditional interpretations of Leibniz, although monads are ultimately immaterial and non-located, material reality and everything in it derives from them and their two main features (Adams, 1994; Baxter, 1995; Rutherford, 1995, 2008; Cover & O’Leary-Hawthorne, 1999; Duarte, 2015, 2017; Look, 2010, 2013; Look & Rutherford, 2007: pp. xix–lxxii; Mercer, 2001; Pearce, 2016; Puryear, 2016; Sleigh, 1990; Whipple, 2017). Not all interpreters entirely agree with this assessment. Some argue that Leibniz held nonidealist views (Arthur, 1998; Bolton, 2004; Broad, 1975; Fichant, 2003; Garber, 1985, 2009; Hartz, 1998, 2007; Hartz & Wilson, 2005; Jolley, 1986; Lodge, 2014; Loptson, 1999; Loptson & Arthur, 2006; Phemister, 1999, 2005). Others argue that Leibniz’s views developed substantially over time or that he never clearly settled on one side or the other (Garber, 2004, 2005, 2009: pp. 382–388; Hartz, 2007; Lodge, 2005; Wilson, 1999). Recently, McDonough (2013) has argued that Leibniz remained deliberately non-committal between idealism and non-idealism and that his deeply held views were compatible with both. At the heart of these disagreements lies Leibniz’s treatment of corporeal substance.1 Despite Leibniz’s frequent claim that the universe ultimately boils down to monads, he also sometimes appears to say that the world’s fundamental furniture includes extended, corporeal substances. Was Leibniz an idealist, then, or not? I do think Leibniz was an idealist. John Whipple (2015, 2017) argues compellingly that some of the apparently anti-idealist passages in Leibniz stem from a range of rhetorical and pedagogical strategies meant to bridge the gap between his idealism and the non-idealism of his interlocutors. When we factor in these strategies, as well as the wider body of work, it seems to me much more likely than not that Leibniz was a firmly committed idealist, especially in his later years. However, even if we grant that Leibniz was an idealist, di\"cult questions remain about his particular brand of idealism. In this chapter, I try to o#er, in the sense of Rutherford 11 LEIBNIZIAN IDEALISM","PeriodicalId":134971,"journal":{"name":"The Routledge Handbook of Idealism and Immaterialism","volume":"247 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0000,"publicationDate":"2021-07-20","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":"0","resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"The Routledge Handbook of Idealism and Immaterialism","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.4324/9781003202851-14","RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":null,"ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"","JCRName":"","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0

Abstract

According to most interpreters, Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz (1646–1716) held a strong form of idealism according to which simple mental substances and their features exhaust fundamental reality. Leibniz called these substances monads (from the Greek word monas, ‘one’ or ‘unit’), and he assigns them two main features: (i) perceptual representations, and (ii) tendencies to move from one set of representations to the next. In more traditional interpretations of Leibniz, although monads are ultimately immaterial and non-located, material reality and everything in it derives from them and their two main features (Adams, 1994; Baxter, 1995; Rutherford, 1995, 2008; Cover & O’Leary-Hawthorne, 1999; Duarte, 2015, 2017; Look, 2010, 2013; Look & Rutherford, 2007: pp. xix–lxxii; Mercer, 2001; Pearce, 2016; Puryear, 2016; Sleigh, 1990; Whipple, 2017). Not all interpreters entirely agree with this assessment. Some argue that Leibniz held nonidealist views (Arthur, 1998; Bolton, 2004; Broad, 1975; Fichant, 2003; Garber, 1985, 2009; Hartz, 1998, 2007; Hartz & Wilson, 2005; Jolley, 1986; Lodge, 2014; Loptson, 1999; Loptson & Arthur, 2006; Phemister, 1999, 2005). Others argue that Leibniz’s views developed substantially over time or that he never clearly settled on one side or the other (Garber, 2004, 2005, 2009: pp. 382–388; Hartz, 2007; Lodge, 2005; Wilson, 1999). Recently, McDonough (2013) has argued that Leibniz remained deliberately non-committal between idealism and non-idealism and that his deeply held views were compatible with both. At the heart of these disagreements lies Leibniz’s treatment of corporeal substance.1 Despite Leibniz’s frequent claim that the universe ultimately boils down to monads, he also sometimes appears to say that the world’s fundamental furniture includes extended, corporeal substances. Was Leibniz an idealist, then, or not? I do think Leibniz was an idealist. John Whipple (2015, 2017) argues compellingly that some of the apparently anti-idealist passages in Leibniz stem from a range of rhetorical and pedagogical strategies meant to bridge the gap between his idealism and the non-idealism of his interlocutors. When we factor in these strategies, as well as the wider body of work, it seems to me much more likely than not that Leibniz was a firmly committed idealist, especially in his later years. However, even if we grant that Leibniz was an idealist, di"cult questions remain about his particular brand of idealism. In this chapter, I try to o#er, in the sense of Rutherford 11 LEIBNIZIAN IDEALISM
Leibnizian理想主义
根据大多数解释者的说法,莱布尼茨(1646-1716)持有一种强烈的唯心主义,根据这种唯心主义,简单的精神物质及其特征耗尽了基本的现实。莱布尼茨称这些物质为单子(来自希腊语monas,意为“一个”或“单位”),并赋予它们两个主要特征:(i)感知表征,(ii)从一组表征转向另一组表征的倾向。在莱布尼茨更传统的解释中,虽然单子最终是非物质的和非定位的,但物质现实和其中的一切都源于它们和它们的两个主要特征(Adams, 1994;巴克斯特,1995;Rutherford, 1995,2008;Cover & O 'Leary-Hawthorne出版社,1999;Duarte, 2015, 2017;看,2010年,2013年;Look & Rutherford, 2007: pp. xix-lxxii;美世,2001;皮尔斯,2016;Puryear, 2016;雪橇,1990;惠普尔,2017)。并非所有口译员都完全同意这种评价。一些人认为莱布尼茨持有非唯心主义观点(Arthur, 1998;博尔顿,2004;广泛,1975;Fichant, 2003;Garber, 1985, 2009;Hartz, 1998,2007;Hartz & Wilson, 2005;乔利,1986;洛奇,2014;Loptson, 1999;Loptson & Arthur, 2006;Phemister, 1999,2005)。另一些人认为莱布尼茨的观点随着时间的推移而发展,或者他从未明确地确定过一方或另一方(加伯,2004年,2005年,2009年:382-388页;哈氏,2007;洛奇,2005;威尔逊,1999)。最近,McDonough(2013)认为莱布尼茨在理想主义和非理想主义之间故意保持中立,他的根深蒂固的观点与两者兼容。这些分歧的核心在于莱布尼茨对有形物质的处理尽管莱布尼茨经常声称宇宙最终归结为单子,但他有时似乎也说,世界的基本家具包括延伸的、有形的物质。那么,莱布尼茨是不是一个唯心主义者呢?我确实认为莱布尼茨是个理想主义者。John Whipple(2015, 2017)令人信服地认为,莱布尼茨的一些明显反理想主义的段落源于一系列修辞和教学策略,旨在弥合他的理想主义和他的对话者的非理想主义之间的差距。当我们考虑到这些策略,以及更广泛的工作,在我看来,莱布尼茨似乎更有可能是一个坚定的理想主义者,尤其是在他的晚年。然而,即使我们承认莱布尼茨是一个唯心主义者,关于他的唯心主义的问题仍然存在。在这一章中,我试图从卢瑟福·莱布尼兹的理想主义的意义上来解释
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
求助全文
约1分钟内获得全文 求助全文
来源期刊
自引率
0.00%
发文量
0
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
确定
请完成安全验证×
copy
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
右上角分享
点击右上角分享
0
联系我们:info@booksci.cn Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。 Copyright © 2023 布克学术 All rights reserved.
京ICP备2023020795号-1
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术官方微信