Socrates’ humour and Plato’s games in the commentaries of late Neoplatonists

Dmitry Kurdybaylo, Inga Kurdybaylo
{"title":"Socrates’ humour and Plato’s games in the commentaries of late Neoplatonists","authors":"Dmitry Kurdybaylo, Inga Kurdybaylo","doi":"10.25205/1995-4328-2022-16-2-493-505","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"The irony of Socrates is one of the essential elements of Plato’s dialogues. However, what appears ironic or playful to modern readers, was not apprehended in the same way by Neoplatonic commentators. For Proclus, one of problematic Plato’s passages concerns the “laborious game,” which refers to the refined eight hypotheses of the Parmenides. Proclus turns to various places of Plato’s dialogues where different games are mentioned. Some of them are mimetic arts, which are partly restricted in Plato’s Republic. Other games are distinguished as pertaining to “old men” and to children: the former is appropriate to philosophers, while the latter is not. Even the “laborious” mode of Parmenides’ playing is given an ontological interpretation. Damascius was aware of the “Parmenides’ game” problem, but he primarily used ready Proclean interpretation. Unsurprisingly, Damascius approaches the conclusion that Parmenides was not playing at all — despite the apparent wording of Plato and minute investigations of Proclus. The extant writings of Simplicius contain no dedicated Platonic commentaries. However, the commentary on Epictetus’ Enchiridion contains a verbose argument on human laughter and its role in a philosopher’s ethos. In general, Simplicius continues Damascius’ trend of rigorous seriousness. Olympiodorus the Younger follows his predecessors in a mere serious reading of Plato, but he acknowledges numerous instances of Socrates’ irony and joking. However, Olympiodorus dissociates Plato from Socrates’ irony and emphasises its purely didactic extent. Generally, we can conclude that the later a Neoplatonic commentator is, the less perceptive to Plato’s humour he appears.","PeriodicalId":228501,"journal":{"name":"ΣΧΟΛΗ. Ancient Philosophy and the Classical Tradition","volume":"15 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0000,"publicationDate":"1900-01-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":"0","resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"ΣΧΟΛΗ. Ancient Philosophy and the Classical Tradition","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.25205/1995-4328-2022-16-2-493-505","RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":null,"ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"","JCRName":"","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0

Abstract

The irony of Socrates is one of the essential elements of Plato’s dialogues. However, what appears ironic or playful to modern readers, was not apprehended in the same way by Neoplatonic commentators. For Proclus, one of problematic Plato’s passages concerns the “laborious game,” which refers to the refined eight hypotheses of the Parmenides. Proclus turns to various places of Plato’s dialogues where different games are mentioned. Some of them are mimetic arts, which are partly restricted in Plato’s Republic. Other games are distinguished as pertaining to “old men” and to children: the former is appropriate to philosophers, while the latter is not. Even the “laborious” mode of Parmenides’ playing is given an ontological interpretation. Damascius was aware of the “Parmenides’ game” problem, but he primarily used ready Proclean interpretation. Unsurprisingly, Damascius approaches the conclusion that Parmenides was not playing at all — despite the apparent wording of Plato and minute investigations of Proclus. The extant writings of Simplicius contain no dedicated Platonic commentaries. However, the commentary on Epictetus’ Enchiridion contains a verbose argument on human laughter and its role in a philosopher’s ethos. In general, Simplicius continues Damascius’ trend of rigorous seriousness. Olympiodorus the Younger follows his predecessors in a mere serious reading of Plato, but he acknowledges numerous instances of Socrates’ irony and joking. However, Olympiodorus dissociates Plato from Socrates’ irony and emphasises its purely didactic extent. Generally, we can conclude that the later a Neoplatonic commentator is, the less perceptive to Plato’s humour he appears.
苏格拉底的幽默和柏拉图的游戏在晚期新柏拉图主义者的评论中
苏格拉底的反讽是柏拉图对话录的基本要素之一。然而,在现代读者看来具有讽刺或戏谑意味的东西,并没有被新柏拉图主义的评论者以同样的方式理解。对于普罗克劳斯来说,柏拉图的一个有问题的段落是关于“费力的游戏”的,它指的是巴门尼德精炼的八个假设。普罗克劳斯在柏拉图的对话中提到了不同的游戏。其中一些是模仿艺术,在柏拉图的《理想国》中有部分限制。其他游戏被区分为与“老人”和孩子有关:前者适合哲学家,而后者则不适合。甚至巴门尼德“辛苦”的游戏模式也被赋予了本体论的解释。大马士革意识到“巴门尼德的游戏”的问题,但他主要使用现成的普罗克lean解释。不出所料,达马西乌斯得出结论,巴门尼德根本不是在玩——尽管柏拉图的措辞很明显,对普罗克劳斯的调查也很细致。辛普利西乌斯现存的著作中没有专门的柏拉图式评论。然而,对爱比克泰德的《恩基里翁》的评论包含了关于人类笑声及其在哲学家精神中的作用的冗长争论。总的来说,辛普利西乌斯延续了大马士革严谨严肃的趋势。小奥林匹亚多罗斯和他的前辈一样,只是认真地阅读柏拉图,但他承认苏格拉底的许多讽刺和开玩笑的例子。然而,奥林匹奥多罗斯将柏拉图与苏格拉底的讽刺分离开来,并强调其纯粹的说教程度。一般来说,我们可以得出这样的结论:新柏拉图主义的评论者越晚,他对柏拉图的幽默就越不敏感。
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
求助全文
约1分钟内获得全文 求助全文
来源期刊
自引率
0.00%
发文量
0
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
确定
请完成安全验证×
copy
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
右上角分享
点击右上角分享
0
联系我们:info@booksci.cn Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。 Copyright © 2023 布克学术 All rights reserved.
京ICP备2023020795号-1
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:604180095
Book学术官方微信