Rorty's Deconstruction of Philosophy

A. O. Agwuele
{"title":"Rorty's Deconstruction of Philosophy","authors":"A. O. Agwuele","doi":"10.1080/17496977.2004.11417765","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"metaphysical principles nor do they require systematic epistemological views. Thus, they have no need for correspondence theories and equally feel no urge to devise any scheme for correlating cognitive processes with the external world. Truth to pragmatists is simply, \"what is good for us to believe\".29 It is a kind of consensus held by the members of a community, that is, an intersubjective agreement that may be subject to change as soon as better ideas and vocabularies emerge. The pragmatist conception puts both knowledge and truth in the same intellectual brace: making truth or knowledge a body of beliefs or self-descriptions which people hold about themselves at any point in time. Consequently, any inquiry into the nature of knowledge or truth necessarily leads the inquirer to a satisfactory account of how a group of people in any culture arrived at the beliefs they presently hold. An inquiry such as this, to pragmatists, must not be tied to any set of criteria for settling arguments or views. To do this will amount to rendering \"the behaviour of others at least minimally reasonable by our lights\".3o Pragmatists do not accept as objective, the rationality that attempts to make a culture intelligible based on external criteria. The pragmatist and antirepresentationalist point of view of Rorty which we have been examining so far, which is a consequent development of his epistemological behaviourism, is a critique of the epistemology that is based on the governing metaphors (vocabularies) and the use of the mind to grapple external objects in the world. Rorty Winter 2004 denies that the world, mind, and vocabularies can be correlated m causal terms. This antirepresentationalist position, subverts our normative conceptions of truth, rationality and science. Rorty posits that each of these has applications within specific contexts and should not be treated as universal. Rorty's position, which suggests that representationalism be dismissed mainly because it has proven to create pseudo-problems, is itself problematic. For instance, the assertion that history has shown every attempt at representation to be fruitless is too sweeping. One can argue that events from the ancients to our day show that exploring the correlation between mind and reality or between statement and non-linguistic items has been linked to some insights, if not empirically, at least intellectually. We now know more about knowing and knowledge than was ever the case before. We now have psychology and many other sub-disciplines of science, which investigate this correlation and have generated so many concepts that make us better informed. Therefore, it is difficult to grant in general that every attempt to relate reality and mind has or will necessarily lead to pseudo-problems. Moreover, the term pseudoproblem itself is a relative one. It is impossible to determine what to all philosophers and branches of philosophy constitute pseudo-problems without having some ideas about what real problems are. Therefore, representationalists argue, that antirepresentationalism should be justified on other grounds than fear of pseudo-problems. It is nonetheless important to realize, as Rorty would have us do, that every transcendental thought geared towards correlating mind or language and reality cannot always fruitfully yield coherence . .>\\ny belief to the contrary is indeed an illusion. If Rorty's epistemological behaviourism and antirepresentationalism are placed together, both of which seek to pragmatically let us know that rationality should be dependent on societal conventions of encountering reality: it will not be surprising at all, that he is accused of relativism. Of course, the insights he provides in these themes, to the extent that they undermine universal rationality, warrant a charge of relativism. This charge naturally follows, when he makes the mind a product of a language game and treats language as a social contingence confmed to its cultural dynamics. Consequently, this enables him to be able to remove the a priori cover provided by mind and language, which sustains the notions of \"foundation of knowledge\" and \"theory of representation\". In other words, by arguing that, if we stop to perceive the mind as mirror and language as accurate representation, we will have no more need for necessary truths, he sounds like a","PeriodicalId":360014,"journal":{"name":"Intellectual News","volume":"28 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0000,"publicationDate":"2004-12-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":"1","resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"Intellectual News","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.1080/17496977.2004.11417765","RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":null,"ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"","JCRName":"","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1

Abstract

metaphysical principles nor do they require systematic epistemological views. Thus, they have no need for correspondence theories and equally feel no urge to devise any scheme for correlating cognitive processes with the external world. Truth to pragmatists is simply, "what is good for us to believe".29 It is a kind of consensus held by the members of a community, that is, an intersubjective agreement that may be subject to change as soon as better ideas and vocabularies emerge. The pragmatist conception puts both knowledge and truth in the same intellectual brace: making truth or knowledge a body of beliefs or self-descriptions which people hold about themselves at any point in time. Consequently, any inquiry into the nature of knowledge or truth necessarily leads the inquirer to a satisfactory account of how a group of people in any culture arrived at the beliefs they presently hold. An inquiry such as this, to pragmatists, must not be tied to any set of criteria for settling arguments or views. To do this will amount to rendering "the behaviour of others at least minimally reasonable by our lights".3o Pragmatists do not accept as objective, the rationality that attempts to make a culture intelligible based on external criteria. The pragmatist and antirepresentationalist point of view of Rorty which we have been examining so far, which is a consequent development of his epistemological behaviourism, is a critique of the epistemology that is based on the governing metaphors (vocabularies) and the use of the mind to grapple external objects in the world. Rorty Winter 2004 denies that the world, mind, and vocabularies can be correlated m causal terms. This antirepresentationalist position, subverts our normative conceptions of truth, rationality and science. Rorty posits that each of these has applications within specific contexts and should not be treated as universal. Rorty's position, which suggests that representationalism be dismissed mainly because it has proven to create pseudo-problems, is itself problematic. For instance, the assertion that history has shown every attempt at representation to be fruitless is too sweeping. One can argue that events from the ancients to our day show that exploring the correlation between mind and reality or between statement and non-linguistic items has been linked to some insights, if not empirically, at least intellectually. We now know more about knowing and knowledge than was ever the case before. We now have psychology and many other sub-disciplines of science, which investigate this correlation and have generated so many concepts that make us better informed. Therefore, it is difficult to grant in general that every attempt to relate reality and mind has or will necessarily lead to pseudo-problems. Moreover, the term pseudoproblem itself is a relative one. It is impossible to determine what to all philosophers and branches of philosophy constitute pseudo-problems without having some ideas about what real problems are. Therefore, representationalists argue, that antirepresentationalism should be justified on other grounds than fear of pseudo-problems. It is nonetheless important to realize, as Rorty would have us do, that every transcendental thought geared towards correlating mind or language and reality cannot always fruitfully yield coherence . .>\ny belief to the contrary is indeed an illusion. If Rorty's epistemological behaviourism and antirepresentationalism are placed together, both of which seek to pragmatically let us know that rationality should be dependent on societal conventions of encountering reality: it will not be surprising at all, that he is accused of relativism. Of course, the insights he provides in these themes, to the extent that they undermine universal rationality, warrant a charge of relativism. This charge naturally follows, when he makes the mind a product of a language game and treats language as a social contingence confmed to its cultural dynamics. Consequently, this enables him to be able to remove the a priori cover provided by mind and language, which sustains the notions of "foundation of knowledge" and "theory of representation". In other words, by arguing that, if we stop to perceive the mind as mirror and language as accurate representation, we will have no more need for necessary truths, he sounds like a
罗蒂的哲学解构
形而上学的原则也不需要系统的认识论观点。因此,他们不需要对应理论,同样也不急于设计任何将认知过程与外部世界联系起来的方案。对实用主义者来说,真理就是“相信对我们有益的东西”它是一种由社区成员持有的共识,也就是说,一种主体间的协议,一旦有更好的想法和词汇出现,这种协议可能会发生变化。实用主义的概念把知识和真理放在同一个智力支柱中:使真理或知识成为人们在任何时间点对自己持有的信念或自我描述。因此,对知识或真理本质的任何探究,必然会使调查者对任何文化中的一群人是如何形成他们目前持有的信仰得出满意的解释。对于实用主义者来说,这样的调查不应该与任何一套解决争论或观点的标准挂钩。这样做将相当于“在我们看来,他人的行为至少是最低限度的合理”。实用主义者不接受以外部标准为基础,试图使一种文化变得可理解的合理性。到目前为止,我们一直在研究罗蒂的实用主义和反表征主义观点,这是他的认识论行为主义的后续发展,是对认识论的批判,认识论是基于控制隐喻(词汇)和使用心灵来抓住世界上的外部对象。罗蒂·温特(2004)否认世界、思想和词汇可以用因果关系联系起来。这种反表征主义的立场,颠覆了我们对真理、理性和科学的规范观念。罗蒂认为,这些都在特定的背景下有应用,不应该被视为普遍的。罗蒂的立场认为,表征主义之所以被摒弃,主要是因为它已被证明会制造伪问题,这一立场本身就是有问题的。例如,断言历史表明,每一次代表的尝试都是徒劳的,这太笼统了。人们可以争辩说,从古代到我们今天的事件表明,探索思想与现实之间或陈述与非语言项目之间的相关性,即使不是经验上的,至少也是智力上的,也与一些见解有关。我们现在比以往任何时候都更了解知识和认知。我们现在有心理学和许多其他科学分支,它们研究这种相关性,并产生了许多概念,使我们更好地了解情况。因此,一般来说,很难承认每一次将现实和精神联系起来的尝试都必然会导致伪问题。此外,伪问题本身是一个相对的问题。如果不知道什么是真正的问题,就不可能确定对所有哲学家和哲学分支来说什么是伪问题。因此,表征主义者认为,反表征主义应该以其他理由为理由,而不是出于对伪问题的恐惧。尽管如此,重要的是要认识到,正如罗蒂希望我们做的那样,每一个旨在将心灵或语言与现实联系起来的先验思想,并不总是能产生有效的一致性……任何相反的信念,实际上都是一种幻觉。如果把罗蒂的认识论行为主义和反表征主义放在一起,这两者都试图在实用主义上让我们知道,理性应该依赖于与现实相遇的社会习俗:他被指责为相对主义一点也不奇怪。当然,他在这些主题中提供的洞见,在一定程度上破坏了普遍理性,因此有理由指责他是相对主义。当他将思维视为语言游戏的产物,并将语言视为一种与文化动态相一致的社会偶然事件时,这种指责自然随之而来。因此,这使他能够去除由思想和语言提供的先验的覆盖物,这种覆盖物支撑着“知识的基础”和“表征论”的概念。换句话说,他认为,如果我们不再将心灵视为镜子,不再将语言视为准确的表征,我们将不再需要必要的真理,他听起来像是
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
求助全文
约1分钟内获得全文 求助全文
来源期刊
自引率
0.00%
发文量
0
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
确定
请完成安全验证×
copy
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
右上角分享
点击右上角分享
0
联系我们:info@booksci.cn Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。 Copyright © 2023 布克学术 All rights reserved.
京ICP备2023020795号-1
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:604180095
Book学术官方微信