你究竟是谁?哲学家对人的本质和起源的探索

IF 0.2 0 RELIGION
Joshua Rasmussen
{"title":"你究竟是谁?哲学家对人的本质和起源的探索","authors":"Joshua Rasmussen","doi":"10.56315/pscf12-23rasmussen","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"WHO ARE YOU REALLY? A Philosopher's Inquiry into the Nature and Origin of Persons by Joshua Rasmussen. Downers Grove, IL: IVP Academic, 2023. 304 pages. Paperback; $30.00. ISBN 9781514003947. *In this text, philosopher Joshua Rasmussen attempts to understand the nature of human persons (Part One) and their origin (Part Two) through a study of human consciousness. While his book is an exercise in philosophical analysis, he offers reflections on the plausibility of his arguments in light of recent findings in psychology and theoretical physics. *In the first two chapters, Rasmussen establishes the framework for his analysis. Of particular significance is his use of introspection to argue against reductionist accounts of consciousness. By introspection, he means attention to first-person experience of the data of consciousness, such as thoughts and feelings (pp. 8-10). Such attention shows that the best explanation of consciousness will be one that accounts for the reality of mental states. Since we can have what Rasmussen calls a direct, introspective awareness of mental states, we can know these states are real (pp. 30, 40). *The next four chapters build upon this realist account of the contents of consciousness by attending to thoughts, perceptions, intentions, and values. In each case, Rasmussen concludes that the best way to account for the existence of these mental states is by changing our orientation from a \"mindlessness frame\" to a \"mind-first\" frame (p. 123). So, for example, introspection reveals that thoughts are real, but are not the same as, nor are they simply reducible to, brain states (pp. 57-59). Likewise, introspection reveals that the elements necessary for a free choice--i.e., agency, intention, and options--are present in acts of willing, and that the reality of these mental acts is confirmed insofar as they affect material states (p. 116). In summary, the existence of these various mental states requires a mental context, which is the mind. But since mental states also change, there must be a constant that anchors the mental context, and that anchor is what Rasmussen means by a person. \"Qualities in consciousness depend on the existence of someone with a mind\" (p. 142, emphasis mine). *There is much that is relevant in these chapters to those interested in how science might inform philosophy of mind. In his analysis of thoughts, Rasmussen notes physicist Alex Rosenberg's objection to the existence of a mind (p. 74). Rosenberg's critique provides Rasmussen with an example of how science can help philosophy clarify the question. In this case, the question is what kind of material must exist for thoughts to exist. Introspection reveals the need to posit some \"material\" that cannot be accounted for only by reference to the data of physics. In his analysis of the will, Rasmussen notes that recent studies in neuroscience have found evidence that conscious acts precede the quantifiable brain activity associated with those acts, thus supporting the notion of a free will. Another study found that conscious acts have a significant effect on the brain without contradicting physical laws (pp. 118-19). These and other studies confirm that mental acts, such as conscious intending, affect material states, such as brain activity. *In the final two chapters of Part One, Rasmussen explains the integration of these conscious acts in terms of what he calls the \"conscious substance theory.\" In short, a person is a substance that unifies both mental and material aspects, such that the causal operator is neither a mental nor a material bit, but rather is itself a capacity of the conscious substance. Furthermore, this conscious substance explains the unity of the person (p. 172). On the one hand, a person can be understood only insofar as the conscious states of that person are affirmed as real. As real as these states are, however, they are all just various parts of what makes a person. The nature of a person is not these parts, but rather is the substance that unifies all these parts. Rasmussen here presents what is perhaps his most interesting example of scientific research relevant to understanding his theory of the person. Physicist Carlo Rovelli explains that matter is best understood as informational, not spatial. This allows for the possibility that both minds and bodies are just different aspects of an underlying quantum field (p. 165), a possibility to which he returns later in the book. *In Part Two, Rasmussen attempts to explain the origin of persons by delineating the conditions for its source (chaps. 9-11) and then explaining what might fulfill those conditions (chaps. 12-13). First, he argues that anything capable of generating a conscious substance must itself be conscious (p. 207), it must be a unity that integrates conscious acts (p. 216), and it must be identical over time (pp. 231, 233). Then, Rasmussen employs a notion of emergence to explain the origin of persons in light of these three conditions. He considers and rejects both \"weak\" and \"incongruent\" notions of emergence that would simply reduce consciousness to third-person, mindless bits of matter (pp. 240, 243). Consciousness must be the result of \"strong\" emergence of a sort that he calls \"substance emergence,\" meaning that the material from which a conscious substance emerges must itself have the capacity for consciousness. Substance emergence is not incongruent, since the substance in question is congruent with conscious acts; nor is it weak, since the emergent content of consciousness (e.g., a mental image) is not logically predictable based solely on the conscious substance from which the content emerges (p. 246). *The book's argument culminates in chapter thirteen, in which Rasmussen posits what he calls the \"source substance\" as the origin of persons. The source substance is fundamental, such that it does not emerge from any prior substance; it is conscious, giving it the capacity to generate consciousness; it generates things according to principles and patterns that are intelligible; and it is the substance out of which persons emerge. Rasmussen attempts to show the plausibility of the theory in several ways. First, the \"informational theory of matter\" based on the work of Rovelli (see above) makes sense if the source of all matter is itself a conscious substance and the informational states that constitute matter are themselves the contents of consciousness belonging to the source (pp. 256-58). Rasmussen then explains how a mind-first (as opposed to a mindless) ontology has the advantage of not requiring multiple kinds of substances to explain matter, since a source substance that is conscious can generate both mental and material aspects of reality. Rasmussen sees further support for this possibility in recent psychological studies of perception, which understand \"particles\" to be properties of conscious beings (pp. 260-61). He notes also that a mind-first notion of reality makes sense given that the world is not fundamentally chaotic, but rather is intelligible. Finally, the existence of persons is more plausible if the foundation from which persons emerge is itself personal. Rasmussen concludes the book with a consideration of what he calls the \"destruction problem.\" If mindless matter (which includes the body) cannot construct a conscious substance, then by symmetry the absence of mindless matter cannot destroy a conscious substance. Therefore, persons can exist even after the body associated with that person ceases to exist (p. 277). *Rasmussen intends the book to be accessible to the lay person while maintaining the interest of the specialist, and he partially succeeds in both respects. Some readers might be encouraged by Rasmussen's repeated assertion that it's hard work to ask and answer these deep questions, as well as by his assurances that it will be worth the effort to go where few have dared to tread, though others are just as likely to find these refrains grating and condescending. Those skeptical of Rasmussen's conclusions will appreciate his willingness to take nothing for granted, including his own existence. The result, however, is that the book wades into debates that are unlikely to help the casual reader follow the argument. Those less interested in the baroque concerns of contemporary analytic philosophy can follow the trajectory of the book's argument by reading only the introductory and summary portions of each chapter. *All readers will be served well by the book's most significant contribution to the study of consciousness, which is Rasmussen's insistence upon the indispensable role of attention to the data of consciousness. Much discussion in modern philosophy of mind not only ignores these data but also actively dismisses them, resulting in what philosopher Bernard Lonergan called the \"truncated subject.\" Rasmussen is to be commended for his effort to understand human consciousness through his relentless attention to its contents. *Unfortunately, the effort is severely hampered by a conflation between knowing and looking that permeates the book. Rasmussen's theory of the nature and origin of persons would be immensely strengthened if understanding (i.e., intellect in action) were to be distinguished from adequate seeing, and if the real (i.e., verified intelligibility) were to be -distinguished from that which is adequately seen. Then his -theory of the person qua conscious substance could be affirmed as real even though it cannot be seen. Furthermore, the emergence of such a substance could be understood by analogy with the paradigmatic instance of emergence, that is, the emergence of the act of understanding out of acts of perception. If readers are unable to complement Rasmussen's argument with their own grasp of these distinctions, they are likely to either reject the book's foundational assertions about the reality of their own conscious acts or simply trust Rasmussen that his conclusions are c","PeriodicalId":53927,"journal":{"name":"Perspectives on Science and Christian Faith","volume":"185 1","pages":""},"PeriodicalIF":0.2000,"publicationDate":"2023-12-01","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":"0","resultStr":"{\"title\":\"Who Are You Really? A Philosopher’s Inquiry into the Nature and Origin of Persons\",\"authors\":\"Joshua Rasmussen\",\"doi\":\"10.56315/pscf12-23rasmussen\",\"DOIUrl\":null,\"url\":null,\"abstract\":\"WHO ARE YOU REALLY? A Philosopher's Inquiry into the Nature and Origin of Persons by Joshua Rasmussen. Downers Grove, IL: IVP Academic, 2023. 304 pages. Paperback; $30.00. ISBN 9781514003947. *In this text, philosopher Joshua Rasmussen attempts to understand the nature of human persons (Part One) and their origin (Part Two) through a study of human consciousness. While his book is an exercise in philosophical analysis, he offers reflections on the plausibility of his arguments in light of recent findings in psychology and theoretical physics. *In the first two chapters, Rasmussen establishes the framework for his analysis. Of particular significance is his use of introspection to argue against reductionist accounts of consciousness. By introspection, he means attention to first-person experience of the data of consciousness, such as thoughts and feelings (pp. 8-10). Such attention shows that the best explanation of consciousness will be one that accounts for the reality of mental states. Since we can have what Rasmussen calls a direct, introspective awareness of mental states, we can know these states are real (pp. 30, 40). *The next four chapters build upon this realist account of the contents of consciousness by attending to thoughts, perceptions, intentions, and values. In each case, Rasmussen concludes that the best way to account for the existence of these mental states is by changing our orientation from a \\\"mindlessness frame\\\" to a \\\"mind-first\\\" frame (p. 123). So, for example, introspection reveals that thoughts are real, but are not the same as, nor are they simply reducible to, brain states (pp. 57-59). Likewise, introspection reveals that the elements necessary for a free choice--i.e., agency, intention, and options--are present in acts of willing, and that the reality of these mental acts is confirmed insofar as they affect material states (p. 116). In summary, the existence of these various mental states requires a mental context, which is the mind. But since mental states also change, there must be a constant that anchors the mental context, and that anchor is what Rasmussen means by a person. \\\"Qualities in consciousness depend on the existence of someone with a mind\\\" (p. 142, emphasis mine). *There is much that is relevant in these chapters to those interested in how science might inform philosophy of mind. In his analysis of thoughts, Rasmussen notes physicist Alex Rosenberg's objection to the existence of a mind (p. 74). Rosenberg's critique provides Rasmussen with an example of how science can help philosophy clarify the question. In this case, the question is what kind of material must exist for thoughts to exist. Introspection reveals the need to posit some \\\"material\\\" that cannot be accounted for only by reference to the data of physics. In his analysis of the will, Rasmussen notes that recent studies in neuroscience have found evidence that conscious acts precede the quantifiable brain activity associated with those acts, thus supporting the notion of a free will. Another study found that conscious acts have a significant effect on the brain without contradicting physical laws (pp. 118-19). These and other studies confirm that mental acts, such as conscious intending, affect material states, such as brain activity. *In the final two chapters of Part One, Rasmussen explains the integration of these conscious acts in terms of what he calls the \\\"conscious substance theory.\\\" In short, a person is a substance that unifies both mental and material aspects, such that the causal operator is neither a mental nor a material bit, but rather is itself a capacity of the conscious substance. Furthermore, this conscious substance explains the unity of the person (p. 172). On the one hand, a person can be understood only insofar as the conscious states of that person are affirmed as real. As real as these states are, however, they are all just various parts of what makes a person. The nature of a person is not these parts, but rather is the substance that unifies all these parts. Rasmussen here presents what is perhaps his most interesting example of scientific research relevant to understanding his theory of the person. Physicist Carlo Rovelli explains that matter is best understood as informational, not spatial. This allows for the possibility that both minds and bodies are just different aspects of an underlying quantum field (p. 165), a possibility to which he returns later in the book. *In Part Two, Rasmussen attempts to explain the origin of persons by delineating the conditions for its source (chaps. 9-11) and then explaining what might fulfill those conditions (chaps. 12-13). First, he argues that anything capable of generating a conscious substance must itself be conscious (p. 207), it must be a unity that integrates conscious acts (p. 216), and it must be identical over time (pp. 231, 233). Then, Rasmussen employs a notion of emergence to explain the origin of persons in light of these three conditions. He considers and rejects both \\\"weak\\\" and \\\"incongruent\\\" notions of emergence that would simply reduce consciousness to third-person, mindless bits of matter (pp. 240, 243). Consciousness must be the result of \\\"strong\\\" emergence of a sort that he calls \\\"substance emergence,\\\" meaning that the material from which a conscious substance emerges must itself have the capacity for consciousness. Substance emergence is not incongruent, since the substance in question is congruent with conscious acts; nor is it weak, since the emergent content of consciousness (e.g., a mental image) is not logically predictable based solely on the conscious substance from which the content emerges (p. 246). *The book's argument culminates in chapter thirteen, in which Rasmussen posits what he calls the \\\"source substance\\\" as the origin of persons. The source substance is fundamental, such that it does not emerge from any prior substance; it is conscious, giving it the capacity to generate consciousness; it generates things according to principles and patterns that are intelligible; and it is the substance out of which persons emerge. Rasmussen attempts to show the plausibility of the theory in several ways. First, the \\\"informational theory of matter\\\" based on the work of Rovelli (see above) makes sense if the source of all matter is itself a conscious substance and the informational states that constitute matter are themselves the contents of consciousness belonging to the source (pp. 256-58). Rasmussen then explains how a mind-first (as opposed to a mindless) ontology has the advantage of not requiring multiple kinds of substances to explain matter, since a source substance that is conscious can generate both mental and material aspects of reality. Rasmussen sees further support for this possibility in recent psychological studies of perception, which understand \\\"particles\\\" to be properties of conscious beings (pp. 260-61). He notes also that a mind-first notion of reality makes sense given that the world is not fundamentally chaotic, but rather is intelligible. Finally, the existence of persons is more plausible if the foundation from which persons emerge is itself personal. Rasmussen concludes the book with a consideration of what he calls the \\\"destruction problem.\\\" If mindless matter (which includes the body) cannot construct a conscious substance, then by symmetry the absence of mindless matter cannot destroy a conscious substance. Therefore, persons can exist even after the body associated with that person ceases to exist (p. 277). *Rasmussen intends the book to be accessible to the lay person while maintaining the interest of the specialist, and he partially succeeds in both respects. Some readers might be encouraged by Rasmussen's repeated assertion that it's hard work to ask and answer these deep questions, as well as by his assurances that it will be worth the effort to go where few have dared to tread, though others are just as likely to find these refrains grating and condescending. Those skeptical of Rasmussen's conclusions will appreciate his willingness to take nothing for granted, including his own existence. The result, however, is that the book wades into debates that are unlikely to help the casual reader follow the argument. Those less interested in the baroque concerns of contemporary analytic philosophy can follow the trajectory of the book's argument by reading only the introductory and summary portions of each chapter. *All readers will be served well by the book's most significant contribution to the study of consciousness, which is Rasmussen's insistence upon the indispensable role of attention to the data of consciousness. Much discussion in modern philosophy of mind not only ignores these data but also actively dismisses them, resulting in what philosopher Bernard Lonergan called the \\\"truncated subject.\\\" Rasmussen is to be commended for his effort to understand human consciousness through his relentless attention to its contents. *Unfortunately, the effort is severely hampered by a conflation between knowing and looking that permeates the book. Rasmussen's theory of the nature and origin of persons would be immensely strengthened if understanding (i.e., intellect in action) were to be distinguished from adequate seeing, and if the real (i.e., verified intelligibility) were to be -distinguished from that which is adequately seen. Then his -theory of the person qua conscious substance could be affirmed as real even though it cannot be seen. Furthermore, the emergence of such a substance could be understood by analogy with the paradigmatic instance of emergence, that is, the emergence of the act of understanding out of acts of perception. If readers are unable to complement Rasmussen's argument with their own grasp of these distinctions, they are likely to either reject the book's foundational assertions about the reality of their own conscious acts or simply trust Rasmussen that his conclusions are c\",\"PeriodicalId\":53927,\"journal\":{\"name\":\"Perspectives on Science and Christian Faith\",\"volume\":\"185 1\",\"pages\":\"\"},\"PeriodicalIF\":0.2000,\"publicationDate\":\"2023-12-01\",\"publicationTypes\":\"Journal Article\",\"fieldsOfStudy\":null,\"isOpenAccess\":false,\"openAccessPdf\":\"\",\"citationCount\":\"0\",\"resultStr\":null,\"platform\":\"Semanticscholar\",\"paperid\":null,\"PeriodicalName\":\"Perspectives on Science and Christian Faith\",\"FirstCategoryId\":\"1085\",\"ListUrlMain\":\"https://doi.org/10.56315/pscf12-23rasmussen\",\"RegionNum\":0,\"RegionCategory\":null,\"ArticlePicture\":[],\"TitleCN\":null,\"AbstractTextCN\":null,\"PMCID\":null,\"EPubDate\":\"\",\"PubModel\":\"\",\"JCR\":\"0\",\"JCRName\":\"RELIGION\",\"Score\":null,\"Total\":0}","platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"Perspectives on Science and Christian Faith","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.56315/pscf12-23rasmussen","RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":null,"ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"0","JCRName":"RELIGION","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 0

摘要

你到底是谁?约书亚·拉斯穆森的《哲学家对人的本质和起源的探究》。downners Grove, IL: IVP Academic, 2023。304页。平装书;30.00美元。ISBN 9781514003947。*在这篇文章中,哲学家Joshua Rasmussen试图通过对人类意识的研究来理解人类的本质(第一部分)和他们的起源(第二部分)。虽然他的书是哲学分析的练习,但他根据心理学和理论物理学的最新发现,对他的论点的合理性进行了反思。*在前两章中,Rasmussen为他的分析建立了框架。特别重要的是,他用内省来反驳还原论对意识的描述。通过内省,他的意思是关注第一人称体验的意识数据,如思想和感觉(第8-10页)。这种关注表明,对意识的最好解释将是对精神状态的现实的解释。既然我们可以拥有拉斯穆森所说的对精神状态的直接的、内省的意识,我们就可以知道这些状态是真实的(第30,40页)。*接下来的四章将通过关注思想、知觉、意图和价值来建立对意识内容的现实主义解释。在每一种情况下,Rasmussen总结说,解释这些精神状态存在的最好方法是将我们的取向从“无意识框架”转变为“思维优先”框架(第123页)。因此,例如,内省揭示了思想是真实的,但与大脑状态不同,也不能简单地归结为大脑状态(第57-59页)。同样,内省揭示了自由选择所必需的元素——即:,代理,意图和选择——都存在于意愿行为中,并且这些心理行为的真实性在它们影响物质状态时得到证实(第116页)。总之,这些不同的心理状态的存在需要一个心理环境,也就是心灵。但由于心理状态也会改变,必须有一个常量来锚定心理环境,这个锚就是拉斯穆森所说的人。“意识的品质取决于有思想的人的存在”(第142页,我的重点)。*对于那些对科学如何影响心灵哲学感兴趣的人来说,这些章节中有很多相关的内容。在对思想的分析中,拉斯穆森注意到物理学家亚历克斯·罗森伯格反对心灵的存在(第74页)。罗森博格的批评为拉斯穆森提供了一个例子,说明科学如何帮助哲学澄清这个问题。在这种情况下,问题是什么样的物质必须存在才能使思想存在。内省揭示了需要假设一些不能仅通过参考物理数据来解释的“材料”。在对意志的分析中,拉斯穆森指出,最近的神经科学研究发现,有意识的行为先于与这些行为相关的可量化的大脑活动,因此支持自由意志的概念。另一项研究发现,有意识的行为在不违背物理定律的情况下对大脑产生重大影响(第118-19页)。这些研究和其他研究证实,精神行为,如有意识的意图,会影响物质状态,如大脑活动。*在第一部分的最后两章中,Rasmussen用他所谓的“意识实体理论”解释了这些有意识行为的整合。简而言之,人是一个统一了精神和物质两方面的实体,因此,因果算子既不是精神的也不是物质的,而是意识实体的一种能力。此外,这种有意识的实体解释了人的统一性(第172页)。一方面,只有当一个人的意识状态被确认为真实时,这个人才能被理解。然而,尽管这些状态都是真实的,但它们都只是构成一个人的不同部分。一个人的本质不是这些部分,而是统一所有这些部分的物质。拉斯穆森在这里提出了一个也许是他最有趣的科学研究的例子,这个例子与理解他的人的理论有关。物理学家Carlo Rovelli解释说,物质最好被理解为信息,而不是空间。这就允许这样一种可能性,即思想和身体只是一个潜在量子场的不同方面(第165页),他在书的后面又回到了这种可能性。*在第二部分中,拉斯穆森试图通过描述人的来源的条件来解释人的起源(第二章)。9-11),然后解释什么可能满足这些条件(第11章)。12 - 13)。首先,他认为任何能够产生意识实体的东西本身必须是有意识的(第207页),它必须是一个整合意识行为的统一体(第216页),并且它必须随着时间的推移而相同(第231,233页)。 如果读者无法用自己对这些区别的理解来补充拉斯穆森的论点,他们很可能要么拒绝这本书关于他们自己有意识行为的真实性的基本断言,要么简单地相信拉斯穆森的结论是c
本文章由计算机程序翻译,如有差异,请以英文原文为准。
Who Are You Really? A Philosopher’s Inquiry into the Nature and Origin of Persons
WHO ARE YOU REALLY? A Philosopher's Inquiry into the Nature and Origin of Persons by Joshua Rasmussen. Downers Grove, IL: IVP Academic, 2023. 304 pages. Paperback; $30.00. ISBN 9781514003947. *In this text, philosopher Joshua Rasmussen attempts to understand the nature of human persons (Part One) and their origin (Part Two) through a study of human consciousness. While his book is an exercise in philosophical analysis, he offers reflections on the plausibility of his arguments in light of recent findings in psychology and theoretical physics. *In the first two chapters, Rasmussen establishes the framework for his analysis. Of particular significance is his use of introspection to argue against reductionist accounts of consciousness. By introspection, he means attention to first-person experience of the data of consciousness, such as thoughts and feelings (pp. 8-10). Such attention shows that the best explanation of consciousness will be one that accounts for the reality of mental states. Since we can have what Rasmussen calls a direct, introspective awareness of mental states, we can know these states are real (pp. 30, 40). *The next four chapters build upon this realist account of the contents of consciousness by attending to thoughts, perceptions, intentions, and values. In each case, Rasmussen concludes that the best way to account for the existence of these mental states is by changing our orientation from a "mindlessness frame" to a "mind-first" frame (p. 123). So, for example, introspection reveals that thoughts are real, but are not the same as, nor are they simply reducible to, brain states (pp. 57-59). Likewise, introspection reveals that the elements necessary for a free choice--i.e., agency, intention, and options--are present in acts of willing, and that the reality of these mental acts is confirmed insofar as they affect material states (p. 116). In summary, the existence of these various mental states requires a mental context, which is the mind. But since mental states also change, there must be a constant that anchors the mental context, and that anchor is what Rasmussen means by a person. "Qualities in consciousness depend on the existence of someone with a mind" (p. 142, emphasis mine). *There is much that is relevant in these chapters to those interested in how science might inform philosophy of mind. In his analysis of thoughts, Rasmussen notes physicist Alex Rosenberg's objection to the existence of a mind (p. 74). Rosenberg's critique provides Rasmussen with an example of how science can help philosophy clarify the question. In this case, the question is what kind of material must exist for thoughts to exist. Introspection reveals the need to posit some "material" that cannot be accounted for only by reference to the data of physics. In his analysis of the will, Rasmussen notes that recent studies in neuroscience have found evidence that conscious acts precede the quantifiable brain activity associated with those acts, thus supporting the notion of a free will. Another study found that conscious acts have a significant effect on the brain without contradicting physical laws (pp. 118-19). These and other studies confirm that mental acts, such as conscious intending, affect material states, such as brain activity. *In the final two chapters of Part One, Rasmussen explains the integration of these conscious acts in terms of what he calls the "conscious substance theory." In short, a person is a substance that unifies both mental and material aspects, such that the causal operator is neither a mental nor a material bit, but rather is itself a capacity of the conscious substance. Furthermore, this conscious substance explains the unity of the person (p. 172). On the one hand, a person can be understood only insofar as the conscious states of that person are affirmed as real. As real as these states are, however, they are all just various parts of what makes a person. The nature of a person is not these parts, but rather is the substance that unifies all these parts. Rasmussen here presents what is perhaps his most interesting example of scientific research relevant to understanding his theory of the person. Physicist Carlo Rovelli explains that matter is best understood as informational, not spatial. This allows for the possibility that both minds and bodies are just different aspects of an underlying quantum field (p. 165), a possibility to which he returns later in the book. *In Part Two, Rasmussen attempts to explain the origin of persons by delineating the conditions for its source (chaps. 9-11) and then explaining what might fulfill those conditions (chaps. 12-13). First, he argues that anything capable of generating a conscious substance must itself be conscious (p. 207), it must be a unity that integrates conscious acts (p. 216), and it must be identical over time (pp. 231, 233). Then, Rasmussen employs a notion of emergence to explain the origin of persons in light of these three conditions. He considers and rejects both "weak" and "incongruent" notions of emergence that would simply reduce consciousness to third-person, mindless bits of matter (pp. 240, 243). Consciousness must be the result of "strong" emergence of a sort that he calls "substance emergence," meaning that the material from which a conscious substance emerges must itself have the capacity for consciousness. Substance emergence is not incongruent, since the substance in question is congruent with conscious acts; nor is it weak, since the emergent content of consciousness (e.g., a mental image) is not logically predictable based solely on the conscious substance from which the content emerges (p. 246). *The book's argument culminates in chapter thirteen, in which Rasmussen posits what he calls the "source substance" as the origin of persons. The source substance is fundamental, such that it does not emerge from any prior substance; it is conscious, giving it the capacity to generate consciousness; it generates things according to principles and patterns that are intelligible; and it is the substance out of which persons emerge. Rasmussen attempts to show the plausibility of the theory in several ways. First, the "informational theory of matter" based on the work of Rovelli (see above) makes sense if the source of all matter is itself a conscious substance and the informational states that constitute matter are themselves the contents of consciousness belonging to the source (pp. 256-58). Rasmussen then explains how a mind-first (as opposed to a mindless) ontology has the advantage of not requiring multiple kinds of substances to explain matter, since a source substance that is conscious can generate both mental and material aspects of reality. Rasmussen sees further support for this possibility in recent psychological studies of perception, which understand "particles" to be properties of conscious beings (pp. 260-61). He notes also that a mind-first notion of reality makes sense given that the world is not fundamentally chaotic, but rather is intelligible. Finally, the existence of persons is more plausible if the foundation from which persons emerge is itself personal. Rasmussen concludes the book with a consideration of what he calls the "destruction problem." If mindless matter (which includes the body) cannot construct a conscious substance, then by symmetry the absence of mindless matter cannot destroy a conscious substance. Therefore, persons can exist even after the body associated with that person ceases to exist (p. 277). *Rasmussen intends the book to be accessible to the lay person while maintaining the interest of the specialist, and he partially succeeds in both respects. Some readers might be encouraged by Rasmussen's repeated assertion that it's hard work to ask and answer these deep questions, as well as by his assurances that it will be worth the effort to go where few have dared to tread, though others are just as likely to find these refrains grating and condescending. Those skeptical of Rasmussen's conclusions will appreciate his willingness to take nothing for granted, including his own existence. The result, however, is that the book wades into debates that are unlikely to help the casual reader follow the argument. Those less interested in the baroque concerns of contemporary analytic philosophy can follow the trajectory of the book's argument by reading only the introductory and summary portions of each chapter. *All readers will be served well by the book's most significant contribution to the study of consciousness, which is Rasmussen's insistence upon the indispensable role of attention to the data of consciousness. Much discussion in modern philosophy of mind not only ignores these data but also actively dismisses them, resulting in what philosopher Bernard Lonergan called the "truncated subject." Rasmussen is to be commended for his effort to understand human consciousness through his relentless attention to its contents. *Unfortunately, the effort is severely hampered by a conflation between knowing and looking that permeates the book. Rasmussen's theory of the nature and origin of persons would be immensely strengthened if understanding (i.e., intellect in action) were to be distinguished from adequate seeing, and if the real (i.e., verified intelligibility) were to be -distinguished from that which is adequately seen. Then his -theory of the person qua conscious substance could be affirmed as real even though it cannot be seen. Furthermore, the emergence of such a substance could be understood by analogy with the paradigmatic instance of emergence, that is, the emergence of the act of understanding out of acts of perception. If readers are unable to complement Rasmussen's argument with their own grasp of these distinctions, they are likely to either reject the book's foundational assertions about the reality of their own conscious acts or simply trust Rasmussen that his conclusions are c
求助全文
通过发布文献求助,成功后即可免费获取论文全文。 去求助
来源期刊
自引率
57.10%
发文量
0
×
引用
GB/T 7714-2015
复制
MLA
复制
APA
复制
导出至
BibTeX EndNote RefMan NoteFirst NoteExpress
×
提示
您的信息不完整,为了账户安全,请先补充。
现在去补充
×
提示
您因"违规操作"
具体请查看互助需知
我知道了
×
提示
确定
请完成安全验证×
copy
已复制链接
快去分享给好友吧!
我知道了
右上角分享
点击右上角分享
0
联系我们:info@booksci.cn Book学术提供免费学术资源搜索服务,方便国内外学者检索中英文文献。致力于提供最便捷和优质的服务体验。 Copyright © 2023 布克学术 All rights reserved.
京ICP备2023020795号-1
ghs 京公网安备 11010802042870号
Book学术文献互助
Book学术文献互助群
群 号:481959085
Book学术官方微信