{"title":"From Duty for the Right Reasons","authors":"T. Toppinen","doi":"10.1093/oso/9780198846253.003.0009","DOIUrl":null,"url":null,"abstract":"An action has moral worth when it’s a morally right action and when it is motivated in such a way that its being right is not accidental. When an action is, in this way, non-accidentally right, the agent is morally praiseworthy for doing the right thing. According to the Right Reasons View, an agent performs an action with moral worth, or is praiseworthy for doing the right thing, roughly to the extent that she does the right thing for reasons that make it right to act in this way (e.g., Arpaly, Markovits). According to another kind of view, actions with moral worth spring from the ‘motive of duty,’ or are based on the agent’s justified belief or knowledge that she ought to act in the relevant way (e.g., Sliwa, Johnson King). These are both attractive ideas. But given certain plausible assumptions, these ideas are in tension with each other. Chapter 9 suggests that the extent to which this is so depends on how the nature of moral thought is to be understood, and that certain forms of expressivism—relational expressivism, in particular—allow the pursuit of a reconciliatory approach.","PeriodicalId":354456,"journal":{"name":"Oxford Studies in Normative Ethics Volume 9","volume":"31 1","pages":"0"},"PeriodicalIF":0.0000,"publicationDate":"2019-10-24","publicationTypes":"Journal Article","fieldsOfStudy":null,"isOpenAccess":false,"openAccessPdf":"","citationCount":"1","resultStr":null,"platform":"Semanticscholar","paperid":null,"PeriodicalName":"Oxford Studies in Normative Ethics Volume 9","FirstCategoryId":"1085","ListUrlMain":"https://doi.org/10.1093/oso/9780198846253.003.0009","RegionNum":0,"RegionCategory":null,"ArticlePicture":[],"TitleCN":null,"AbstractTextCN":null,"PMCID":null,"EPubDate":"","PubModel":"","JCR":"","JCRName":"","Score":null,"Total":0}
引用次数: 1
Abstract
An action has moral worth when it’s a morally right action and when it is motivated in such a way that its being right is not accidental. When an action is, in this way, non-accidentally right, the agent is morally praiseworthy for doing the right thing. According to the Right Reasons View, an agent performs an action with moral worth, or is praiseworthy for doing the right thing, roughly to the extent that she does the right thing for reasons that make it right to act in this way (e.g., Arpaly, Markovits). According to another kind of view, actions with moral worth spring from the ‘motive of duty,’ or are based on the agent’s justified belief or knowledge that she ought to act in the relevant way (e.g., Sliwa, Johnson King). These are both attractive ideas. But given certain plausible assumptions, these ideas are in tension with each other. Chapter 9 suggests that the extent to which this is so depends on how the nature of moral thought is to be understood, and that certain forms of expressivism—relational expressivism, in particular—allow the pursuit of a reconciliatory approach.
当一个行为在道德上是正确的并且它的动机不是偶然的时候,这个行为就具有道德价值。当一个行为是非偶然正确时,行为人做了正确的事在道德上是值得赞扬的。根据正确理由观点,行为人的行为具有道德价值,或者说做了正确的事是值得称赞的,大致程度上,她做正确的事是出于使她这样做是正确的原因(例如,Arpaly, Markovits)。根据另一种观点,具有道德价值的行为源于“责任动机”,或者基于行为人的正当信念或知识,即她应该以相关的方式行事(例如,Sliwa, Johnson King)。这两个想法都很吸引人。但考虑到某些看似合理的假设,这些观点彼此之间存在矛盾。第9章指出,这种情况在多大程度上取决于如何理解道德思想的本质,以及某些形式的表现主义——尤其是关系表现主义——允许追求一种和解的方法。